You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Yes, I'm the guy asking a lot of annoying ring theory questions on the category theory community server! :upside_down:
But I want this stuff to become category theory.
So, there are two apparently equivalent definitions of an [[Azumaya algebra]] over a commutative ring :
an algebra for which there's an algebra such that is [[Morita equivalent]] to .
an algebra that's a [[separable algebra]] whose center is .
The first definition is conceptually nice because there's a monoidal bicategory of
where the monoidal structure comes from tensor product of algebras over .
Then the first definition is saying the object is Azumaya iff it's invertible: there's a such that in this monoidal bicategory.
(I believe this implies , but I don't see why. I'd better check: if it doesn't, then there's a paper out there giving a bad definition of Azumaya algebra!)
The second definition sounds less categorical, but actually a separable algebra is one where the multiplication has a section (that is, a right inverse) in the category of -bimodules.
And this is very nice! First, it makes sense very generally: for any monoid object in any monoidal category, we can say it's separable if its multiplication has right inverse in the category of -biactions. Second, this right inverse makes into a [[Frobenius monoid]].
Proving this is easy and fun with string diagrams.
So, my question is whether there's an elegant proof that the two definitions of Azumaya algebra agree... a proof that might be generalized to other contexts.
John Baez said:
The second definition sounds less categorical, but actually a separable algebra is one where the multiplication has a section (that is, a right inverse) in the category of -bimodules.
That's probably a very dumb question, but why isn't the map defined by always a section of the multiplication ?
I think because it is not a map of A,A-bimodules. It sends to , and not .
I think I was mistaken by the fact that and not so that if indeed .
Yes, when I wrote I meant . And yes, is not a map of bimodules.
I see what you meant, I felt funny as well
I decided to delete that "feel funny" business. I don't feel funny anymore. :upside_down:
Say is the algebra of matrices with entries in . Let be the elementary matrices. Then here's a map that's a right inverse for multiplication:
But notice, this only works if we can divide by in .
So it turns out, for example, that the algebra of matrices with entries in a field of characteristic is separable iff is not divisible by .
Thanks, nice example!
Similarly the group algebra of a finite group is separable iff the order of the group is not divisible by the characteristic of the field . Nasty things happen when the order of the group is divisible by the characteristic of the field... and that's why nobody knows all the irreducible representations of symmetric groups over finite fields.
This is a shocking hole in our knowledge, and if climate change weren't a problem and I was king of the Earth I would declare it an emergency. :upside_down:
Is a section given by ?
I'm still not sure if it's a map of -bimodule...
I'm not used at all to bimodules
No, it doesn't work.
A variant of this should work I guess.
I guess, it's more complicated than that and maybe you use the fact that a -linear representation of is the same than a -module ?
Ok, I saw the answer on Wikipedia, and I was very close so a section is
Funny that it provides a Frobenius monoid, so is at the same time a Hopf algebra and a Frobenius algebra...
I'm wondering if there is a class of finite dimensional hopf algebras bigger than such groups algebras which are separable as well because you can define for every Hopf algebra with antipode , now I don't know by what I should replace .
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
Ok, I saw the answer on Wikipedia, and I was very close so a section is
You were not merely close! Your answer
is equal to Wikipedia's, and frankly I like your way of writing it better.
I like this way even better:
since it doesn't involve arbitrarily choosing a trick for summing over all pairs that multiply to give .
I thought to that at first but I wasn't sure that there are elements in the sum, so I wrote it in the other way
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
Is a section given by ?
But this way makes me think that it is maybe a natural map
If I define for a group morphism
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
Funny that it provides a Frobenius monoid, so is at the same time a Hopf algebra and a Frobenius algebra...
I love this fact! They have the same multiplication but different comultiplications. I keep wanting to study this more. I should read this:
Theorem 4.15 says any finite-dimensional Hopf algebra admits a Frobenius algebra structure with the same multiplication. But apparently not every (finite-dimensional) Frobenius algebra has a Hopf algebra structure with the same multiplication.
Oh, now I think that this comultiplication is for a basis of
if is a finite-dimensional hopf algebra such that doesn't divide the characteristic of
That would be even better if this this paper was written for Hopf monoids
So we should define what is a finite-dimensional Hopf monoid in a symmetric monoidal category
and there are good chances that most of the paper will still work
If is an arbitrary Hopf algebra you should be summing over a basis, right? I'm not sure your formula is right in general, but it's definitely right for group algebras.
Oh yes, you're right
You can define a finite-dimensional object in a symmetric monoidal category to be one that is a [[dualizable object]] - that works pretty well.
Ok, nice, we should try to see if some facts work for dualizable hopf monoids in a symmetric monoidal -linear category so
By the way, I fear that business of summing over a basis of the Hopf algebra is not the correct way to define a Frobenius comultiplication on a finite-dimensional Hopf algebra. There's a theory of "integrals" for Hopf algebras, and I think you need to choose an integral for your Hopf algebra to make it into a Frobenius algebra. That's what that paper explains.
Ok, the crux to obtain the Frobenius algebra structure seems to be their fundamental theorem of Hopf modules.
(Theorem 4.13)
Nice.
So, back to my original question. For any -algebra , the following are equivalent:
1) there's an algebra such that is Morita equivalent to
2) is separable and its center is ?
But what's the slickest proof? Can we find a proof that uses just string diagrams or other category-theoretic machinery?
To do this we should try to work in the symmetric monoidal bicategory of
as much as possible, since that may let us generalize to other (sufficiently nice) symmetric monoidal bicategories.
Condition 1) is clearly phrased in terms of this monoidal bicategory : it's just saying that our object has an object that's a "tensor inverse" of .
For condition 2), "separability" is nicely phrased in terms of this bicategory: it's saying that multiplication , viewed as homomorphism of -bimodules, has a right inverse! But what about this business of the center of being ? That sounds hard to express abstractly.
But then I remembered: any separable algebra is a Frobenius algebra! And for any Frobenius algebra (over a field , at least) there's a god-given way to project it down to its center! We comultiply , then use the symmetry to "switch" , and then multiply . This gives an idempotent that projects down to its center. I showed why this works on page 84 here.
So, I think there's a nice way to say the center of is just when is separable. We say this map equals the counit followed by the unit .
So now conditions 1) and 2) are things I can say in any symmetric monoidal bicategory, and I can try to show they're equivalent... or at least show one implication, perhaps.
In 1) the condition that have a tensor inverse is a bit annoying because it has an existential quantifier. But in fact the tensor inverse, when it exists, is always . That could help.
Remark: in 2) the condition of separability has also an existential quantifier. So I guess that we could maybe go from to the section and vice-versa.
That's true. Actually the reason I usually think of "separable algebras" as not having an existential quantifier is that I usually think of the section as part of the structure of a separable algebra, just as I think of the comultiplication as part of the structure of a Frobenius algebra. (And indeed, every separable algebra equipped with a specific section gives a Frobenius algebra with a specific comultiplication!)
But over in condition 1), I am acting like there's no extra structure required. So something is funny. Maybe the point is that instead of simply saying is a tensor inverse of , I should be specifying a specific invertible bimodule from to .
And that's nice because it smells a lot like the section .
So I/we should start calculating and see if I/we can get from condition 1), thus reformulated, to condition 2). Or vice versa. Going from 2) to 1) seems a bit easier.
(I'm willing to work with anyone on this as long as they don't expect me to write a paper with them. It's so tiring to write papers with other people that by now I'd rather just stick their name on the paper and do all the writing myself, or not write a paper at all and let them do whatever they want.)
I'm a bit lost about the nature of the morphisms. The section is a morphism of -bimodule, right? but now you say that is a -bimodule.
John Baez said:
I should be specifying a specific invertible bimodule from to .
I don't understand this phrase.
Maybe you wanted to say "a specific invertible bimodule morphism".
If it's the case, that's exactly what I wanted to suggest too.
Is there a canonical way to build this morphism?
Maybe you wanted to say "a specific invertible bimodule morphism".
No, I meant what I said. It's confusing but in definition 1) we are working in the monoidal bicategory of
so there, when I say is a weak inverse to , I mean that there's a bimodule from the algebra to the algebra , which is an equivalence in this bicategory.
Note that bimodules are the 1-morphisms in this bicategory!
If what I'm saying sounds mysterious, it probably pays to read a little about [[Morita equivalence]].
But I see the nLab starts by explaining Morita equivalence for rings, while I'm using it for -algebras! So that's another way to get confused. :upside_down:
Yes, in fact if I understand two -algebras and are Morita equivalent if there is an equivalence in our bicategory, is it right? and I don't want to read more and be confused.
Now, I guess that the definition of an equivalence in a bicategory is obtained by generalizing the equivalence of categories in the bicategory in terms of objects, 1-morphisms and 2-morphisms in any bicategory?
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
Yes, in fact if I understand two -algebras and are Morita equivalent if there is an equivalence in our bicategory, is it right? and I don't want to read more and be confused.
About reading, I mean that most of the time it is incredibly more efficient when someone explains you shortly what you want to know in the terms you want to use rather than getting confused by 10 equivalent definitions that are not formulated in the language you prefer. That's not that I'm too lazy to read.
John Baez said:
(I'm willing to work with anyone on this as long as they don't expect me to write a paper with them. It's so tiring to write papers with other people that by now I'd rather just stick their name on the paper and do all the writing myself, or not write a paper at all and let them do whatever they want.)
I don't know a lot about ring and modules, and I enjoy more writing stuff alone too because that's the only way I can understand some subject. So if you think to me, I would be happy to prove a categorical version of this equivalence, if you had enough energy to answer my questions. That would be a very nice way for me to get my hands on more pure math stuff. Now, I still don't have enough information to do this work. I don't know how to define the section 2) from equivalence 1) and how to define the equivalence 1) from the section 2).
Maybe if you knew a reference where this equivalence is proved in the classical case of rings, I could understand how to do it by reading.
I think people have a hard time working with me or supervising me because I always want to have my own catch on the stuff.
I just try to get as much information from people to learn faster :grinning_face_with_smiling_eyes: and after I want to use it by myself
Well, I think you wanted somebody to help you and not help somebody and lose a lot of time with that :upside_down:
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
Yes, in fact if I understand two -algebras and are Morita equivalent if there is an equivalence in our bicategory, is it right? and I don't want to read more and be confused.
Yes. But like lots of people doing bicategories or 2-categories I use to indicate the existence of a 1-morphism that's an equivalence, and to indicate the existence of a 2-morphism that's an isomorphism.
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
Now, I guess that the definition of an equivalence in a bicategory is obtained by generalizing the equivalence of categories in the bicategory in terms of objects, 1-morphisms and 2-morphisms in any bicategory?
Right.
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
About reading, I mean that most of the time it is incredibly more efficient when someone explains you shortly what you want to know in the terms you want to use rather than getting confused by 10 equivalent definitions that are not formulated in the language you prefer.
More efficient for you, sometimes less efficient for the person who has to explain it.
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
Now, I still don't have enough information to do this work. I don't know how to define the section 2) from equivalence 1) and how to define the equivalence 1) from the section 2).
The problem is precisely to figure out those things - if it's possible at all. If I knew those things I wouldn't need help.
Ahah okay, but it is maybe in papers (for the classical case). I've found one of them when this equivalence is written saying it's a classical result but it doesn't give the proof. It says to look at the bibliography of one of the reference. For the moment, I still haven't found the proof but it may be doable.
Azumaya categories theorem 1.2 is your equivalence
(for commutative rings)
Okay, thanks. I'd probably like to spend at least a few hours trying to figure it out myself before looking at this.
There isn't a proof just the proposition.
There is a proof of something which looks similar in the book "Théorie de la descente et Algèbres d'Azumaya", Théorème 5.1. p.93
They prove that 1') "There exists a -algebra B and a faithfully projective -module such that as -algebras." is equivalent to 2) " is separable and its center is ."
I guess that 1') should be equivalent to 1) if you know a bit how to manipulate bimodules.
Just to save it for myself: they say that 1') is equivalent to 1) in Lemme 7.1 p.26 and refer to H. Bass, Algebraic K-theory, 1968 for a proof.
@John Baez: have you looked at Borceux–Vitale's Azumaya Categories? My impression is that they give the kind of general categorical proof you are looking for (see Theorem 3.4).
Oh, I see now that Jean-Baptiste also mentioned this paper.
I have looked at it, but I looked at it again 10 minutes ago (before reading you comment!) and noticed that it says this:
Starting from the seventies, several categorical approaches to Azumaya algebras and the Brauer group have been proposed (see the bibliography in [23] for some references). Almost all these approaches deal with Azumaya monoids in a monoidal category V. If one confines one's attention to monoids (i.e. one-object V-categories), the basic results needed to develop the Azumaya-Brauer theory are quite simple: they reduce essentially to Morita theory in monoidal categories. Consequently, the conditions on V can be weaker than those assumed in our paper. For example, in the classical paper by Pareigis [20], the closedness of V is weakened, and in some recent papers by Van Oystaeyen and Zhang (see [22]) and by Alonso Alvarez et al. (see [1]), V is braided but not necessarily symmetric; however, some completeness and biclosedness requirements are needed on V.
So I looked at [23]:
On the top of page 4 this lists four equivalent definitions of an Azumaya algebra in classic case of -algebras, including the two I'm interested in, and threatens to generalize these to "Azumaya monoids" in a pretty general symmetric monoidal category. So that's what I want!
So, I just need to figure out what they're doing.
They use very weak assumptions: they're looking at monoids in a symmetric monoidal category with coequalizers that are preserved by tensor products.
Note than in definition 3.1, c) they define a a splitting monoid as a (non-unital) monoid which have a section of the "canonical map" and such that this section and multiplication verify the comultiplication/multiplication diagram of a Frobenius monoid.
I'm a little bit confused by the fact that they use the tensor product and I'm not sure what is this canonical map.
I'm not even sure what means in a general monoidal category.
This is why they need the coequalizers that I mentioned!
If is a monoid in a monoidal category with coequalizers, and acts on the right on and acts on the right on , you can define a thing using a coequalizer, copying the usual construction when .
Namely, you form the two obvious morphisms and you coequalize them.
Ok, and acts on the right on means that you have a morphism which verifies the same diagrams than for a set which would act on a monoid , right?
Yes, exactly.
So in a symmetric monoidal category with equalizers preserved by taking tensor products with objects, we can talk about:
and finally the monoidal bicategory of
This is a pretty general context for Azumaya--Brauer--Morita theory.
Nice, I think I understand how to define this stuff! Just a question: do you really mean "right adjunctions" or is it "right actions"?
I meant actions. Interesting mistake - you can see how much I type "adjunctions"! I'll fix that, for other people reading.
This abstract theory is very pretty and I'm basically glad people developed it to the point of defining "Azumaya monoids" in a bunch of equivalent ways.
But I still think there should be a simple string diagram proof that these two concepts are equivalent:
1) a monoid in for which there's a monoid such that in the monoidal bicategory of monoids, bimodules and bimodule homomorphisms.
2) a monoid that's separable (it's equipped with a section of the multiplication map in the category of -bimodules) and central: the canonical map projecting down to its center (defined using ) has image .
Item 2) could be somewhat wrong, and Vitale says it rather differently in that paper I linked to. After Proposition 1.3 he says a monoid is Azumaya if and only if it is faithfully projective in the category of -bimodules and the canonical arrow is an isomorphism.
Here he's assuming is a closed symmetric monoidal category, and is the internal hom. He uses a weird symbol for it... but not a lollipop.
Hmm I know how to draw string diagrams about monoids in a symmetric monoidal category, now I'm not sure how to draw the bimodules between them and the bimodule homorphisms.
You can draw string diagrams in any bicategory, by shading the regions with objects. Believe it or not, this is actually explained on Wikipedia. (I keep telling people that whenever I learn anything I start by reading Wikipedia.)
Ok, nice if you want to work in a generic bicategory. But in fact here, it's not complicated to write string diagrams about bimodules between monoids in a symmetric monoidal category. You just have to write diagrams for the actions which are of the same form than the ones for the monoids.
So now, maybe you can add big arrows for the bimodules morphisms and success to write all your equations.
I'm not sure about this last sentence.
You're right: the fact that we're dealing with a bicategory of bimodules of monoids in a symmetric monoidal category means we have a choice of how to draw things! The supposedly equivalent conditions 1) and 2) may be best drawn in two different styles, and then we'd need to show how those styles are related.
It would be nice to reduce a bunch of this Azumaya-Brauer-Morita theory to pictures!
Sure!
To start, we can very well draw in string diagrams what are two monoids , an -bimodule and a morphism of -bimodules, in a symmetric monoidal category.
I drew it here
John Baez said:
On the top of page 4 this lists four equivalent definitions of an Azumaya algebra in classic case of -algebras, including the two I'm interested in, and threatens to generalize these to "Azumaya monoids" in a pretty general symmetric monoidal category. So that's what I want!
Note that the treatment in Azumaya Categories is more general: instead of working with monoids in a monoidal category , which are one-object -categories, they work with arbitrary -categories.
Yes. It's very cool. I added a discussion Azumaya categories to the nLab article [[Azumaya algebra]], along with some other stuff. But I don't think I need this generalization for what I'm trying to do.
I think there is no problem to express in string diagrams that 1) There exists an equivalence for a monoid and 2) there exists a section of such that followed by the symmetry followed by the multiplication is equal to the counit followed by the unit .
I have just one question. What is the definition of this counit?
Also, I'm not sure that a proof using the basic string diagrams of symmetric monoidal categories will be shorter. But it will be more visual for sure!
I think it must be easy to verify if "there exists an equivalence " and "there exists an equivalence " are equivalent using these string diagrams.
At least I can try to prove it. If it's false, it will be more difficult to prove that it is false.
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
If it's false, it will be more difficult to prove that it is false.
If it's true, it will be even more difficult to prove that it is false! :grinning_face_with_smiling_eyes:
A lemma that is super easily seen with string diagrams is that and so (because ().
( is the monoid obtained by taking the object , you keep the same unit, but you do a twist before the multiplication of .)
And the multiplication of is obtained by writing and using the two multiplication to arrive to
Also and I believe that every -bimodule is also a -bimodule (with same underlying object).
and every -bimodule morphism induces a -bimodule morphism
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
I think there is no problem to express in string diagrams that 1) There exists an equivalence for a monoid and 2) there exists a section of such that followed by the symmetry followed by the multiplication is equal to the counit followed by the unit .
I have just one question. What is the definition of this counit?
That's a tricky and interesting question. I am most familiar with the case when our symmetric monoidal category is the category of finite-dimensional vector spaces over a field so let me talk about that case first. Then is a finite-dimensional algebra over a field. In this case we can always define a counit as follows:
where for any the map is given by left multiplication
You may enjoy showing
in this context.
It's easy to generalize this to the case where is any symmetric monoidal category and is any monoid whose underlying object has a dual . That is, it's easy if you know about duals of objects in symmetric monoidal categories, and how they are used to define traces!
As with any adjunction, the dual of an object in a symmetric monoidal category comes along with morphisms called the unit and counit, which are unfortunately completely different from the things I was calling the unit and counit here:
there exists a section of such that followed by the symmetry followed by the multiplication is equal to the counit followed by the unit .
So let me use some other names! Our object and its dual - which I'm assuming exists :warning: - come with morphisms
often called the unit and counit, obeying the [[triangle identities]].
Because is a monoid with with multiplication we can form this composite:
And this is the thing I was calling .
In the long composite above I'm using the symmetry .
It's a fun exercise to check that when is a monoid in the symmetric monoidal category of finite-dimensional vector spaces, this definition of agrees with the one I mentioned before:
where for any the map is given by left multiplication
In short: we get whenever has a dual. So the next question is: why, in our general abstract nonsense situation, should an Azumaya monoid have a dual?
But that's a bit hard too, and I'm worn out for now.
By the way, I find this thing:
to be much clearer using string diagrams. I did a bunch of related string diagram calculations on pages 82-85 here.
Thanks for the explanations! I'm a bit tired right now me too, I'll try to understand all of this a bit later!
A correction:
John Baez said:
Say is the algebra of matrices with entries in . Let be the elementary matrices. Then here's a -bimodule homomorphism
that's a right inverse for multiplication:
But notice, this only works if we can divide by in .
In fact there's an -bimodule homomorphism that's a right inverse for multiplication even if we can't divide by .
The trick is to define it by
where we don't sum over .
Then, for it to be a left -module homomorphism it must do this:
For it to be a right -module homomorphism it must do this:
Luckily these agree. So we use this as our rule for the map, and it's easy to see that multiplication sends back to .
This choice of splitting is scarily arbitrary since it depends on a choice of .
To avoid the arbitrariness we could sum over all and then divide by ... which is what I suggested before... but that only works if is invertible in our ring .
Okay, I've been a bit silent because I was trying to make sense of traces and I can't figure out why if and are morphisms such that is dualizable, then . I have seen graphical proofs in the context of compact closed categories but I don't succeed to understand how to translate these drawings in equations or commutative diagrams.
Hi! It's very tiring to explain all the rules for translating string diagrams in compact closed categories into equations or commutative diagrams when you're in an environment where it's hard to draw pictures, like we are here. So I won't try.
This particular proof is something that's incredibly beautiful with string diagrams: the "cyclic property of the trace", is proven just by cycling things around, using the fact that the trace is defined using a loop.
But... okay, here's an explanation on Qiaochu Yuan's excellent blog:
I don't know if it will help you - but by the way, I've been getting a lot of good information about separable algebras from his blog, and I think every mathematician who likes categories and algebra should read his blog.
Ah thanks! I've seen the pictures that make the morphisms turning around but I want to see how it comes from the equations, so I'm going to read that.
He claims to explain it.
Okay, I think my earlier remarks involving the center of a separable algebra were a bit wrong-headed. I think this paper has a better idea:
I'm used to working with finite-dimensional separable algebras over a field, and there I can freely use the duals of those algebras - that is, their dual vector spaces - and the fact that finite-dimensional vector spaces form a [[compact closed category]]. But working over a general ring, or in a general symmetric monoidal category, it becomes questionable whether we're allowed to assume our separable algebras have duals.
There's even the question of whether separable algebras over a field are automatically finite-dimensional or not!
It seems they are - but the proof is rather hard:
This is different from [[Frobenius algebras]], where it's really easy to see they are finite-dimensional. All the [[separable algebras]] I really understand well are Frobenius algebras. These two concepts are deeply related, as you can see from the nLab articles (which I helped write back when I was using these algebras to study TQFT).
But when @Jean-Baptiste Vienney asked me to cough up the counit for an arbitrary separable algebra, I choked! Even working over a field, I couldn't do it without assuming the algebra is finite-dimensional!
Luckily, Vitale has a better approach. Let's work in a [[Benabou cosmos]] , meaning a symmetric monoidal closed category with small limits and colimits. A cosmos is a gold-plated sort of category that makes everything nice. We can reduce the assumptions later if we actually prove anything interesting!
In a cosmos , Vitale claims the following are equivalent:
Now, the second one looks rather scary and technical to me, but I'm slowly learning to love it.
For starters, the category of -bimodules is monoidal closed, so it has an internal hom, which I'm denoting by .
(If you don't like bimodules remember that an -bimodule is the same as an -module, so bimodules can be seen as a special sort of modules. And in a symmetric monoidal category that's a cosmos, I'm pretty sure any monoid has a closed monoidal category of modules!)
The property that is an isomorphism is very strong, in the category of finite dimensional vector space, it means that is one-dimensional... if I'm not mistaken.
You didn't yet read my explanation of what I meant by .
If I meant the internal hom in then you'd be correct.
Let me explain what is actually like when . (By the way, finite-dimensional vector spaces don't form a cosmos. It's not a big deal, but it's worth noting.)
So, when , is an algebra, and is the algebra of all linear maps that are actually -bimodule endomorphisms:
Every left -module endomorphism of is right multiplication by some element of , so we know
for some fixed .
Then implies in the center of !
Oh, I see, ok, I was thinking to -bimodule endomorphisms.
Okay.
So: is just the center of in this case!
Ohhh, so this condition is the one that the center of is like before, it makes sense!
Right: saying the "obvious" map (I hope it's actually obvious) is an isomorphism, is saying that the center of consists just of scalars, i.e. elements of , where is our field.
But I don't think I used anything special about fields here; I believe everything I just said works when is modules of any commutative ring .
So in this class of examples - the "classical" examples - we have a nice way of saying that the center of our -algebra is just .
Such algebras are called central.
So, in general, we'll say a monoid is central when the obvious morphism of -bimodules is an isomorphism!
Here's a question I don't know how to answer, though the first few steps are clear:
Puzzle 1. - if are central monoids in a cosmos , is central?
In the case where , this is true. And it's also easy to see that the tensor product of Azumaya monoids is Azumaya, so if 1. and 2. are really equivalent (like Benabou and Vitale claim), it's at least reasonable to hope that the tensor product of central monoids is central, even though it doesn't actually follow, since an Azumaya monoid is a central monoid with some extra property.
If someone digs into Puzzle 1 they'll probably start wondering how is related to and . Just remember that means something different in each expression!!!
John Baez said:
Right: saying the "obvious" map (I hope it's actually obvious) is an isomorphism, is saying that the center of consists just of scalars, i.e. elements of , where is our field.
Actually it's not so obvious. We have in the category of -bimodules and so you obtain by monoidal closure and then you compose with the unit to get your map .
If I'm not mistaken.
Also, I don't see what, in the case of algebras over a field, this -bimodule map is supposed to be!
We've seen is the center of .
But there's not a very good map from an algebra to its center, except in some special cases (like commutative algebras :upside_down:).
I'm currently thinking :upside_down:
Your abstract argument getting a map from to looks convincing, but since I don't see what it gives in the "classical example" I'm afraid there's some confusion floating around here....
This thing of looking at bimodules over algebras over a commutative ring instead of just modules over the commutative ring makes my brain burning.
I always forget what are the "base rings".
Right. I mentioned that bimodules over algebras are really just modules over (other) algebras:
John Baez said:
(If you don't like bimodules remember that an -bimodule is the same as an -module, so bimodules can be seen as a special sort of modules.
So, to think about bimodules over algebras over a commutative ring, you can just think about modules over an algebra over a commutative ring. And those behave a lot like modules over a not necessarily commutative ring.
If we couldn't stack ideas on top of other ideas like this we wouldn't be category theorists. :upside_down:
That burning sensation actually means you are growing new neurons.
Aaaah good, so I don't suffer for nothing.
Is [A,-] a right adjoint here?
Or does it not make sense to consider [A,-] as a functor here, with [A,A] as merely one value of it?
Thanks for asking! It's supposed to be some sort of internal hom, right adjoint to some tensor product. It's described in item v on page 96 here:
using notation that's too baroque for me to reproduce here, and not very well explained.
From the notation I assumed this [-,-] thing was an internal hom in the monoidal category of A,A-bimodules, or equivalently modules.
So I would guess that is right adjoint to the endofunctor , where is the tensor product of -bimodules.
But now that you mention it, that can't be right! The endofunctor is just the identity on the category of -bimodules, so its right adjoint is just the identity!
So, if this is what Vitale meant, we'd have , and what he's claiming doesn't make sense.
He's claiming that when the ambient symmetric monoidal category is , is the center of the algebra .
So I'm pretty sure that what he means is this: if and are -bimodules, is the set of -bimodule morphisms from to . This set has its own -bimodule structure, unless I'm going insane.
With this interpretation really is the center of .
But if this is what Vitale means, what is right adjoint to, if anything??? I'm left asking @David Michael Roberts's question.
John Baez said:
So I'm pretty sure that what he means is this: if and are -bimodules, is the set of -bimodule morphisms from to . This set has its own -bimodule structure, unless I'm going insane.
Okay, so I was going insane. The set of -bimodule morphisms from to is only an -bimodule when is commutative.
For example suppose is an -bimodule morphism:
Then multiplying on the left (or right) by an element ruins this property:
So, given a monoid in the cosmos and -bimodules and in this cosmos, I believe Vitale wants to be the -object of -bimodule morphisms from to . It's not an -bimodule itself, just an object in .
However, is better: it's a monoid object in !
And so it has a unit .
And this fact, I believe, give the so-called "obvious" map that I was mentioning:
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
John Baez said:
Right: saying the "obvious" map (I hope it's actually obvious) is an isomorphism, is saying that the center of consists just of scalars, i.e. elements of , where is our field.
Actually it's not so obvious.
It's like the old joke where a professor says something is obvious, the student asks him if it's really obvious, and the professor goes away, comes back three days later and says "yes, it's obvious".
I just saw this discussion so I haven't had the time to read all the arguments (so I apologise if I missed something making this irrelevant), but I think you may be interested in this preprint that came out a few days ago, especially sections 5.5 and 6 addressing this issue in monoidal -categories.
Thanks! That looks helpful even though I'm not ready to plunge into an -categorical treatment!
I had not seen this before.
I have been making a lot of progress this week thanks in part to this paper:
and thanks in part to conversations with Todd Trimble.
I'd like to outline some thoughts and state some theorems and conjectures that deserve nice simple proofs (if they're correct).
Let me start by reviewing the basic ideas, which make sense at a high level of generality. Then I'll state some theorems and conjectures in the case of algebras over commutative rings. Maybe some of you can help find nice proofs and/or generalize them.
Whoops, first I have to take a walk. :big_frown:
Okay, let me start with the general context. Let's take V to be a very nice symmetric monoidal category: closed, complete and cocomplete. This is what Benabou called a cosmos.
There is then a bicategory VMod where:
I will try to remember to write for V-profunctors and for V-enriched functors (or V-functors, for short).
I don't know good references for these facts:
Theorem 1 VMod is a symmetric monoidal bicategory.
Theorem 2. VMod is compact closed.
Here's a good place to see the definitions spelled out:
The example that looms large in my mind is V = RMod, the category of modules of a commutative ring, with the usual tensor product of modules giving the symmetric monoidal structure.
In this case
When V = RMod we can more generally call a V-enriched category an algebroid over R, but there's vastly more literature on algebras.
I'm trying to understand Azumaya algebras, but the general concept is this:
Definition. A V-category C is Azumaya if there is a V-category D such that C D I in VMod.
Here is the tensor product of V-enriched categories and I is the unit for this tensor product. So Azumaya V-categories are, morally speaking, the invertible ones.
But notice that stands for equivalence in the bicategory VMod, so Azumaya V-categories need only be invertible up to equivalence.
My goal, ultimately, is to find nice proofs of a bunch of facts about Azumaya V-categories. Some of these facts are already known. One-object Azumaya V-categories where V = RMod for a commutative ring are called Azumaya algebras and there are some very interesting theorems about these.
Now I already said that VMod is compact closed. This means that every V-category has a dual which comes with a unit
and counit
which obey the usual triangle identities up to isomorphism.
In other words, they form a biadjunction. (The isomorphisms I alluded to can always be improved to obey some laws of their own called the 'swallowtail identities' - but this may not ever matter to us, though it would be fun for me if it did.)
Now, there's another fundamental result that I don't know a reference for:
Theorem 3. Any two duals of an object in a symmetric monoidal bicategory are equivalent. Given a V-category , the opposite V-category , defined in a way analogous to the usual opposite of a category, serves as a dual for in VMod.
John Baez said:
Okay, let me start with the general context. Let's take V to be a very nice symmetric monoidal category: closed, complete and cocomplete. This is what Benabou called a cosmos.
Is it really necessary to suppose to be complete and cocomplete to prove your results? Is it sufficient to only suppose that is finitely complete and finitely cocomplete? In this case, you could also chose for example.
I am not going to try to find minimal assumptions for my results! It's important, but it would clutter the big picture I'm trying to paint. The proofs of the results will show us what the minimal assumptions are; these may vary from result to result.
To repeat and expand on what I said:
Theorem 3. Given a V-category , the opposite V-category , defined in a way analogous to the usual opposite of a category, serves as a dual for in VMod. The counit
can be taken to be the hom of , which is the V-functor
hom:
Furthermore, we can twist around this V-profunctor and get the unit
John Baez said:
I am not going to try to find minimal assumptions for my results! It's important, but it would clutter the big picture I'm trying to paint. The proofs of the results will show us what the minimal assumptions are; these may vary from result to result.
(Ok, my intuition is that all of this will not use any "infinity" but I'm maybe mistaken. Mathematicians often suppose that some category is "complete" or "cocomplete" instead of simply supposing that all the limit and colimit they use exist which would be better.) But that's a bit out of subject, sorry, just a side note.
Next, yet another result I don't know a reference for:
Theorem 4. If C, D are objects in a symmetric monoidal bicategory and C D I, then we can find a unit and counit making D into a dual of C.
John Baez said:
Theorem 1 VMod is a symmetric monoidal bicategory.
One way to prove this, which I unsurprisingly happen to think is nice and clean, is to combine Framed bicategories and monoidal fibrations with Constructing symmetric monoidal bicategories. In example 15.4 of FBMF I observed that if you make a symmetric monoidal category indexed/fibered over in the canonical way by taking families of objects, then it is frameable so you can make it into a double category, and then that double category has local coequalizers so you can take the double category of monoids and modules therein, which is your . In the symmetric case all the monoidal structures carry through, so you can then apply CSMB to make the symmetric monoidal double category into a symmetric monoidal bicategory.
This fact was of course known to category theorists (particularly Australians) long before my papers, but I don't actually know of another place where it is proven carefully.
Jean-Baptiste Vienney said:
(Ok, my intuition is that all of this will not use any "infinity" but I'm maybe mistaken. Mathematicians often suppose that some category is "complete" or "cocomplete" instead of simply supposing that all the limit and colimit they use exist which would be better.)
If you want a bicategory whose objects are arbitrary small -categories, then you need to have arbitrary small colimits in order to define composition of -profunctors. You can get away with finite colimits if you restrict the objects of to be -categories with finitely many objects. Or you can try to use something like a [[virtual double category]] instead, but that doesn't work so well for duality theory.
John Baez said:
Theorem 2. VMod is compact closed.
...
Theorem 3. Given a V-category , the opposite V-category , defined in a way analogous to the usual opposite of a category, serves as a dual for in VMod.
I'm not sure how one could prove theorem 2 without proving theorem 3 (which should have theorem 2 as an immediate consequence). One fairly early reference for this is section 7 of Day & Street's Monoidal bicategories and Hopf algebroids (1997), but they don't give any more details of the proof than you did. I don't offhand know of somewhere that gives more details.
John Baez said:
Theorem 4. If C, D are objects in a symmetric monoidal bicategory and C D I, then we can find a unit and counit making D into a dual of C.
I don't think I knew that (did I?). I find it very surprising. I guess it must use the symmetry fundamentally somehow? It's certainly not true that if and are functors and then they are adjoint.
Thanks for all your comments, which will help me a lot if I ever write something up, e.g. on the nLab .
You're right that Theorem 3 is how to prove Theorem 2; I was going for the gradual reveal.
I hope Theorem 4 is right. The idea is to take an equivalence
and take a weak inverse and compose it with the symmetry to get an equivalence
and then finagle around until we get a dual of in the sense I defined. I'll try to scribble out a string diagram proof.
Now, if Theorems 1-4 are true, we can conclude:
Corollary 5. A V-category is Azumaya iff its hom, made into a V-profunctor from to , is an equivalence in VMod.
The direction is obvious but the direction uses Theorems 2-4 and (if it's true) it's a useful condition for Azumayaness, since it means we don't have to run around looking for a weak inverse to : if it exists, it's the opposite -category!
I'll quit now... but so far I'm just warming up.
Now is a great time for people to raise questions, raise objections, provide more references, or (dis)prove Theorem 4!
John Baez said:
I hope Theorem 4 is right. The idea is to take an equivalence and take a weak inverse and compose it with the symmetry to get an equivalence ...
Oh, of course! Once you have both and , then you just need the fact that any equivalence can be improved to an adjoint equivalence.
(Applied in the delooping of your monoidal bicategory to a tricategory.)
In Corollary 5, do you mean to refer to the hom as a profunctor from to ? Writing it as a functor doesn't indicate its domain and codomain qua profunctor, it could equally be a profunctor from to .
By the way, have you looked at Niles Johnson's paper Azumaya Objects in Triangulated Bicategories? His characterization theorem 1.6 seems to be along the lines that you're talking about.
Mike Shulman said:
In Corollary 5, do you mean to refer to the hom as a profunctor from to ? Writing it as a functor doesn't indicate its domain and codomain qua profunctor, it could equally be a profunctor from to .
I meant the hom is a profunctor from to . I was forgetting the latex to write to indicate we've got a profunctor here, and sort of hoping I wouldn't need to introduce that notation.
**[EDIT: I later gave up, went back, and tried to consistently use for enriched profunctors and for enriched functors.)
Mike Shulman said:
John Baez said:
I hope Theorem 4 is right. The idea is to take an equivalence and take a weak inverse and compose it with the symmetry to get an equivalence ...
Oh, of course! Once you have both and , then you just need the fact that any equivalence can be improved to an adjoint equivalence.
Right. For anyone who wants to see a string diagram proof of what we're talking about here, try the pictures in the proof of Theorem 14 on page 19 here. Here we've got a monoidal category where every object has an object with isomorphisms , and we improve one of those isomorphisms in order to make into the dual of - i.e., in order to get isomorphisms obeying the [[triangle identities]]. The argument is visually quite pretty.
So what I'm doing now is the same argument, but with all the equations in the string diagram calculation replaced by isomorphisms.
Mike Shulman said:
By the way, have you looked at Niles Johnson's paper Azumaya Objects in Triangulated Bicategories? His characterization theorem 1.6 seems to be along the lines that you're talking about.
Oh yes, this looks like exactly what I was trying to do! My Corollary 5 proved the equivalence between Johnson's conditions iv and v. But what I'm really shooting for is the equivalence between ii and v: the connection between Azumaya algebras and central separable algebras, worked out at a high level of generality.
I don't feel heartbroken that Johnson already did this, because this equivalence is already visible, at least in a special case, in this paper I was reading (thanks in part to @Nathanael Arkor):
and I'm just trying to understand it enough that I can use it for what I'm really trying to do: some nefarious scheme I'll reveal in the fullness of time.
So I'll just keep on here, now with a lot of help from Niles Johnson.
So let's pick up here:
John Baez said:
Corollary 5. A V-category is Azumaya iff its hom, made into a V-profunctor from to , is an equivalence in VMod.
and see more concretely what happens when that hom, viewed as a V-profunctor, is an equivalence.
I think now I'll break down and use to mean is a V-profunctor and to mean is a V-functor, at least for a while.
So, any V-profunctor is (by definition) a V-functor from to , which amounts to the same thing as V-functors from to , the V-category of V-functors from to V.
is called the category of V-enriched presheaves on .
By a spinoff of the enriched Yoneda lemma, V-functors from to in turn amount to the same thing as cocontinuous V-functors from to .
So, the symmetric monoidal bicategory I've been calling VMod, where
is equivalent to one where
So we get a new viewpoint on VMod. From this new viewpoint, what does it mean to say a V-category is Azumaya?
In the old viewpoint is Azumaya if its hom, made into a V-profunctor from to , is an equivalence in VMod.
Don't you mean a -profunctor from to , the unit -category?
Yes. Thanks:
In the old viewpoint is Azumaya if its hom, made into a V-profunctor from to , is an equivalence in VMod.
In the new viewpoint it means this. By the universal property of , we can take the hom V-functor
and extend it to a cocontinuous V-functor
Then is Azumaya iff this cocontinous V-functor is an equivalence.
Let's summarize and look at an example:
Corollary 6. A V-category is Azumaya iff when we extend the V-functor to a cocontinuous V-functor , then is an equivalence of V-categories.
Since this looks a bit scary let's do the example where is the category of modules of some commutative ring R and is a one-object V-category. As we've seen, such a one-object V-category amounts to the same thing as an (associative unital) R-algebra, say A.
Then is the V-category of right modules of A.
Similarly the one-object V-category is what we'd normally call the R-algebra . So the monstrosity is what we'd normally call the V-category of right modules of - or better yet, the V-category of -bimodules.
So this scary-looking thing
maps any A,a-bimodule to some R-module. And if you unwind all the abstractions you see it works like this: it maps any A,A-bimodule to the R-module , which consists of all A,A-bimodule endomorphisms of M.
In summary, we've gotten this:
Corollary 6. For a commutative ring R, an R-algebra A is Azumaya iff the enriched functor sending any A,A-bimodule to its R-module of A,A-bimodule endomorphisms is an equivalence.
So that was an example! But category theory is the subject where the examples need examples. So let's do an example of this corollary.
Let's take R to be the ring of real numbers. Since is the boldest of rings we call it .
And let's take our -algebra A to be - you guessed it! - the quaternions, .
A good example of an bimodule is .
consists of all -bimodule endomorphisms of .
By the ring theory analogue of Cayley's theorem, all the left -module endomorphisms of are given by right multiplication by guys in . And all the right -module endomorphisms of are given by left multiplication by guys in .
So every bimodule endomorphism is just multiplication by some element of the center of !
But the center of is just , so we get
So far I haven't used anything special about the quaternions. But next, every -bimodule is isomorphic to a sum of copies of .
Similarly, every -module is a sum of copies of .
And sends the sum of copies of to the sum of copies of since it's cocontinuous.
So with a little work we can show is an equivalence from the (enriched) category of -bimodules to the (enriched) category of -modules.
So, by Corollary 6, the quaternions are an Azumaya algebra over the reals!
This may not be the slickest way to show that fact... but this example is helping me understand Corollary 6.
John Baez said:
Here is the tensor product of V-enriched categories and I is the unit for this tensor product, which is just V itself. I'm just writing it as I to emphasize that Azumaya V-categories are, morally speaking, the invertible ones.
No. The unit V-category, , is the V-category with one object with hom-object being , the monoidal unit in .
I don't think this really affects anything you wrote, just that some of your s need to be s. The confusion there is aided and abetted by the fact that you were not distinguishing V-functors and V-profunctors in your notation. :stuck_out_tongue_wink:
So the hom V-functor
corresponds to the unit and counit profunctors
Yes, I was confused about versus for a while until Mike set me straight.
I was hoping to only talk about enriched profunctors and not need to draw two kinds of arrows, but eventually I started wanting to talk about enriched functors too. So I'm really working with a symmetric monoidal double category. I might as well admit it. I've tried to go back, fix things, and write for profunctors.
One comment about your . This is the set of 2-morphisms . In my old terminology this is the 'diagonal trace' of the identity 1-cell on , or the 'diagonal dimension' of , as we think of the trace of the identity as giving the dimension.
If we are thinking of Vmod as a bicategory then a priori this 2-hom should be a set. However, for 'nice' bicategories, the hom-categories, like have a canonical enrichment in the category of scalars , and for Vmod this category of scalars is precisely .
I don't remember ever talking about something called [A,A]. But this thread is pretty long!
Oh, I see, it's way back in the "old" part of the thread before I started a slightly more systematic treatment.
Btw it's really good to quote stuff with the links included so people (including forgetful people who wrote that old stuff, like me) can click and go back and look at it!
John Baez said:
- Monoids that are faithfully projective in the category of -bimodules and have the property that the obvious morphism in the category of -bimodules is an isomorphism.
In this case I thought you were excited about so I wouldn't have expect you to have forgotten about it. :upside_down:
John Baez said:
So, when , is an algebra, and is the algebra of all linear maps that are actually -bimodule endomorphisms:
Thanks! Yeah, I'm still trying to reach various equivalent characterizations of Azumaya algebras, like that one... but starting on May 31 I decided it's better to be a bit more systematic and explain a lot of stuff that's mostly in these papers:
Francis Borceux and Enrico Vitale, Azumaya categories, Applied Categorical Structures 10 (2002), 449-467.
Niles Johnson, Azumaya Objects in Triangulated Bicategories.
Simon Willerton said:
In this case I thought you were excited about so I wouldn't have expect you to have forgotten about it. :upside_down:
I didn't forget the thought but I certainly wouldn't have any special memory of something with so bland a name as .
If you read on you'll see that later I later wound up calling this thing . There was a fairly good reason at the time but I'll forget that notation too in a few days.
Anyway, thanks for pointing out that this thing is the hom from to itself in our big bicategory! It's cool how your "two 2-traces" get into the picture here!
Okay, let's keep going!
Before I dive into "central" and "separable" algebras and their generalizations to V-categories, I want to mention a nice result for R-algebras, meaning associative unital algebras over some commutative ring R.
Theorem 7. The A,B-bimodule M is a left adjoint in the bicategory of R-algebras, bimodules and bimodule homomorphisms iff M is finitely generated and projective as a left B-module.
This is stated without proof as Proposition 2.3 in Borceux and Vitale's Azumaya categories. By now @Todd Trimble has given me a couple of proofs: "ring theorist's proofs" that use known stuff about algebras and their modules, and "category theorist's proofs" that use the conceptual description of finitely generated projective B-modules as precisely those lying in the [[Cauchy completion]] of the one-object RMod-category B.
I still want to understand this result better, but for now let's see what we can do with it.
By definition A is Azumaya iff there's an equivalence
in our bicategory of V-categories, V-profunctors and V-natural transformations where V = RMod.
I've also pointed out that we can assume without loss of generality that comes from the hom-functor .
But we can always enhance any equivalence in a bicategory to an adjunction, in fact taking either arrow to be the left adjoint and massaging the other until it becomes the right adjoint. So as a consequence of all these facts we get
Corollary 8. An R-algebra A is Azumaya iff the V-profunctor coming from the hom V-functor is a left adjoint equivalence.
So assume A is Azumaya. By Theorem 7, we must have
for some left , right module which is finitely generated and projective!
But every object in any monoidal bicategory is automatically a left I-module in just one way (up to isomorphism) so we don't even need to bother saying "left I".
A right -module is the same as an -bimodule, if that makes you feel better.
So the main takeaway is that whenever we've got an Azumaya algebra , there's a finitely generated projective object in the category of -bimodules that attests to this.
But we don't have to roam around the universe looking for this . After all, we knew that came from the hom of .
So this -bimodule must be something canonically associated to itself.
But the most obvious -bimodule associated to is just ! So I'll guess that is just .
Is that right?
John Baez said:
So assume A is Azumaya. By Theorem 7, we must have
for some left , right module which is finitely generated and projective!
I'm a little confused by this. But maybe I'm just not keeping up. Are you now in the situation where you put a hat on, but you've stopped putting a hat on? Is this in the bicategory of functors between module categories rather than bimodules between algebras? The latter you called Vmod, but I don't know if you gave the latter a name.
Anyway, certainly in the bicategory of bimodules between algebras over , the which 'comes from hom' is where the subscripts denote which algebra acts on which side. Then when we move it into the bicategory of functors between modules categories it becomes .
Aside/Digression: You said that if is Azumaya then the centre of is isomorphic to . I note that that's the same as saying the 'diagonal dimension' of is .
Is it true that the abelianization (commutativization?) of is also isomorphic to ? So is ?
We have a compact closed symmetric monoidal bicategory so we can take the 'categorical trace' of any 1-endomorphism and this trace is an object in the category of scalars . I call this the 'round trace' as it looks like a circle when you draw it in string diagrams. In particular we can take the round trace of the identity 1-morphism. The identity morphism is the bimodule and its round trace (aka the round dimension of ) is precisely the abelianization of .
But the round trace of the identity should just be the composite where the arrows are , the symmetry and . The arrows are all equivalences, so the composite, ie the trace, should be (quasi) invertible in . What's that going to be, other than ? :smiley: (Well, maybe something else interesting!)
Here invertible means with respect to the composition monoidal product in which corresponds to the tensor product of -modules in .
Simon Willerton said:
Is it true that the abelianization (commutativization?) of is also isomorphic to ? So is ?
Are you quotienting by the two-sided ideal generated by or just the -submodule? The first one is what I would call the abelianization but the second is the one that might work. For example, the quaternions () are a division algebra so the first one would necessarily yield but the second one yields .
Reid Barton said:
Are you quotienting by the two-sided ideal generated by or just the -submodule? The first one is what I would call the abelianization but the second is the one that might work. For example, the quaternions () are a division algebra so the first one would necessarily yield but the second one yields .
What I want is . So that means modding out by the -submodule .
It is not an algebra itself, so 'abelianization' is probably a bad term, I agree! It's like a space of coinvariants.
Another term for it zeroth Hochschild homology , which is overkill here, but gives some context.
What's a better name?
(And that's a nice example.)
If is regarded as a one-object enriched category, then this is the coend of its hom-functor, i.e. its [[trace of a category]].
Oh, oops, I missed that you already said that.
But what's wrong with that as a name?
I meant a better name in the algebraic context, a better name than abelianization. It is an example of a categorical trace, but that's not what an algebraicist would call it, I doubt.
I expect an algebraist would probably call it . (-:
Simon Willerton said:
John Baez said:
So assume A is Azumaya. By Theorem 7, we must have
for some left , right module which is finitely generated and projective!
I'm a little confused by this. But maybe I'm just not keeping up. Are you now in the situation where you put a hat on, but you've stopped putting a hat on? Is this in the bicategory of functors between module categories rather than bimodules between algebras? The latter you called VMod, but I don't know if you gave the former a name.
Yes, it looks like I was being sloppy, but you guessed correctly. This here is a 1-morphism in the bicategory of cocontinuous functors between module categories. It came from a like-named 1-morphism in the bicategory of bimodules between algebras, which is an equivalent bicategory.
To confuse you more, I decided to also call this bimodule .
The point was: since this 1-morphism is a left adjoint, by Theorem 7 the bimodule must be finitely generated and projective as a module over one of the two algebras that acts on it.
(Which one? That, alas, involves some conventions which I had messed up.)
Anyway, certainly in the bicategory of bimodules between algebras over , the which 'comes from hom' is where the subscripts denote which algebra acts on which side. Then when we move it into the bicategory of functors between modules categories it becomes .
Okay, great. I got incredibly confused about this for a while, which is why I left it as a question.
To add to the confusion, I got tangled up in the question of whether our module categories should be left module categories or right module categories! Ultimately I got pressured by various forces to use right module categories, but I didn't get it all straightened out. So for consistency with myself I should probably have written
for some left , right module .
Anyway, when all is said and done, I believe the upshot is this:
Theorem 9. Suppose is an Azumaya algebra over the commutative ring . Then the counit is an equivalence hence a left adjoint, so is finitely generated and projective as a right -module (i.e. an -module). Furthermore the unit is an equivalence hence a left adjoint, so is finitely generated and projective as a right -module.
If anyone was paying careful attention, they'll see I'm trying to correct some earlier mistakes here:
while
For Azumaya algebras these are both true. Over a field, the first just says any Azumaya algebra must be finite-dimensional. The second is a bit more exciting.
So, we make up a definition:
Definition. An algebra over a commutative ring is separable if it is f.g. projective as an -module.
But every algebra is finitely generated as an -module since it's generated by 1: every element is 1 times something in .
So people usually just say
Definition. An algebra over a commutative ring is separable if it is projective as an -module.
Then there's an equivalent characterization which is quite practical and looks very beautiful in terms of string diagrams! This is what I really like:
Theorem 10. An algebra over a commutative ring is separable if and only if the multiplication has a section (= right inverse) that is an -bimodule homomorphism.
Notice that -bimodules and homomorphisms between these are equivalent to -modules and homomorphisms between these; I'm just sick of writing that "op". I'm treating as an -bimodule like this:
Proof of Theorem 10. : For any algebra multiplication gives an epimorphism
in the category of -bimodules. Since is the free -bimodule on one generator, if has a section
then is a summand of a free -bimodule, hence it's projective. (If you know these facts for modules but not bimodules, remember that
: If is projective as an -bimodule, the epimorphism
splits, and the splitting is our desired section . :purple_square:
More on this later. Next:
Simon Willerton said:
Aside/Digression: You said that if is Azumaya then the centre of is isomorphic to . I note that that's the same as saying the 'diagonal dimension' of is .
Is it true that the abelianization (commutativization?) of is also isomorphic to ? So is ?
I don't know!
We have a compact closed symmetric monoidal bicategory so we can take the 'categorical trace' of any 1-endomorphism and this trace is an object in the category of scalars . I call this the 'round trace' as it looks like a circle when you draw it in string diagrams. In particular we can take the round trace of the identity 1-morphism. The identity morphism is the bimodule and its round trace (aka the round dimension of ) is precisely the abelianization of .
Or in still other words, is there some natural morphism from the composite
to
that could make the latter into a monoid in ?
And you're conjecturing it's the identity because this is the only element that every group has. :upside_down:
Which is a perfectly sound strategy.
But we could get more evidence for this if we saw that this zeroth Hochschild homology of our Azumaya algebra is not only a weakly invertible object in the category of -bimodules but also a monoid object in there.
Does that seem right? In other words: is there some natural algebra structure on the zeroth Hochschild homology of an algebra, or at least an Azumaya algebra?
Or in other words, is there some natural "multiplication" going from the composite
to the composite
?
John Baez said:
Does that seem right? In other words: is there some natural algebra structure on the zeroth Hochschild homology of an algebra, or at least an Azumaya algebra?
In general, the zeroth Hochschild homology of an algebra is not an algebra. The zeroth Hochschild cohomology of an algebra is an algebra in general - it's the centre of the algebra, which is a subalgebra.
Anyway, there's a result of Cortiñas and Weibel in Homology of Azumaya algebra
For a commutative ring , if A is an Azumaya R-algebra, then for , and
.
This is another way of saying .
Nice!
So, we can wonder if there's a slick way to prove this for people who like bicategories of enriched profunctors.
Or, perhaps using the fact that Azumaya algebras are the same as central separable algebras over . My spidey senses tell me that for a separable algebra we should have , so if it's also central we get . But I only know for sure that in the case of separable (or more generally semisimple) algebras over a field.
Hello all! Earlier this month @John Baez told me about this discussion and asked me some questions. So here I am! John asked specifically if I can come up with some string diagram proofs of the equivalence between various definitions of Azumaya object. One barrier to doing that is that I had to figure out how the proof goes again! I'm pleasantly surprised my 2014 paper on this [Joh14] is finding some use, but it's been long enough that I'm a little annoyed at how some of it is written.
So, to make myself feel better, I figured out what I think is a better explanation of the key step. I still don't know how to make string diagrams for the proof (and I have some doubts about whether it's possible) but I thought at least I could explain the non-string proof here in case someone else wants to try.
(Warning: I'm about to paste in a bunch of comments; apologies to anyone that I'm inadvertently annoying!)
Here's the setup: Suppose M is a symmetric monoidal bicategory with two additional features. (1) a closed structure, and (2) an autonomous structure. Autonomous means that there is an (-)^{op} operation that switches source/target of 1-cells, like taking op of a category or regarding a left A-module as a right A^{op} module. (I don't think this is enough explanation for someone who isn't familiar with this stuff, but I'm going to skip it unless someone would like me to say more.)
I'll write the monoidal product of M with a dot, like A.B, just for ease of reading and typing. We'll also need composition of 1-cells, and I'll write that as juxtaposition, like FG = F \circ G. One of the decisions I now find annoying in that 2014 paper is that I used "diagrammatic composition"; I'm not going to do that here. So, in this explanation, FG means first apply G, and then F.
I'll write k for the monoidal unit of M. I'll also pretend that the unit constraints for k are identities. I don't love doing that, but I think I won't type the rest of this if I have to work out the unit stuff carefully. (There will be some other points where I'll have to be a bit glib; apologies in advance.)
For an object A of M, I'll say A is invertible as a 0-cell if there exists an object B such that A.B is equivalent (in the bicategorical sense) to k. This means there are 1-cells P: A.B → k and R: k → A.B with PR and RP being isomorphic to the respective identities. (I think some people call this Morita-invertible or something like that, because that's what it means in the classical algebra case. I called it Eilenberg-Watts equivalence in [Joh14].)
I'll denote the unit 1-cell of A as 1 or 1_A. The autonomous structure also lets us regard 1_A as a 1-cell k → A.A^{op}, and I'll write [A] for that. (There is also the other-sided version, which I thankfully won't have to use.)
The central/separable definition of Azumaya algebras is equivalent to [A] being invertible as a 1-cell. That means there is another 1-cell T: A.A^{op} → k such that [A]T and T[A] are isomorphic to the respective identities. I confess I didn't read all of the above discussion carefully, but I think that's the part that people have been figuring out.
I know there's a lot more to say about invertibility and adjoint invertibility, and how the presence of a closed structure interacts with that, but I'm skipping it (a) because some of that is discussed above, (b) it's more than I want to write now, and (c) I don't think it's the key step.
The Key Step I want to explain here is this: If A is invertible as a 0-cell, then [A] is invertible as a 1-cell. In [Joh14] this is the implication (v) ⇒ (i) for Theorem 1.6, and there are two paragraphs about it on page 14. Here, I want to split the explanation into three lemmas.
All of the lemmas refer to 1-cells in M:
Only the middle lemma uses the autonomous structure of M, and none of them use the closed structure. (That's needed for connecting to the other ways of defining Azumaya.)
I can add proofs of these lemmas if there is interest. but for now I'll just give the gist of the argument.
Lemma 0 (Eckmann-Hilton)
Consider the composite . There is an isomorphism
(Note: this isn't exactly correct as stated, because the right-hand side doesn't have the same source/target as the left hand side; so there are some implicit unit constraints here. But this isomorphism is the main thing.)
A more precise version is Lemma 3.2 in [Joh14].
Proof idea: basically it's pseudofunctoriality of the monoidal product in M.
Lemma 1
Suppose . Then .
Proof idea: This is basically a duality argument that (I think) is standard at least in some circles. It involves tracking the isomorphism in the hypothesis through the equivalence .
(Then there is also more unit stuff , that I am again skipping.)
Lemma 2
If is an invertible pair of 1-cells between and , and if for some 1-cells
Then is an invertible pair of 1-cells between and .
Proof idea: Lemma 2 is the most involved one. The isomorphism is just associativity plus . The isomorphism is basically the long chain of isomorphisms displayed on page 14 of [Joh14]. It uses the Eckmann-Hilton lemma plus some psuedofunctoriality of , associativity, more unit stuff, and . (I got a little stuck on this at first because I thought I needed Eckmann-Hilton twice, but it's just once, at the beginning.)
Now the Key Step I mentioned above is easy to explain. I tried to use the notation of [Joh14] where possible, in case that's useful for someone. If A is invertible as a 0-cell, then we have
with
Let and . Then by Lemma 1 we have
Next, observe
(Again I'm being a little glib, since the target of [A.B] is , so one needs some symmetries here too.)
Now use Lemma 2, with and . The conclusion is that is an invertible pair, with .
That's basically the end of the explanation, but I can add more if someone would like. As I said above, I don't really know how to make string diagrams for these, but it seems like the Lemmas would be the key place to start trying.
Oh, edit to add: Why don't I know how to make string diagrams for these? I'm familiar with some string diagrams where adjacent strings mean composition of 1-cells, and some others where adjacent strings mean monoidal products in a 1-category (which is also composition of 1-cells in the associated 1-object bicategory). But I don't know about diagrams where one can show both composition and a separate monoidal product. Maybe something more in the realm of surface diagrams is needed, or some fancier string diagrams that I don't know about.
Thanks a lot! Don't worry about writing too much: it's very easy for people here to "mute" threads they don't want to read.
It will take me a while to absorb what you wrote! For starters, am I correct that now you're using "autonomous" to mean what's also called "compact closed"? Mike Stay (for example) wrote a paper on compact closed symmetric monoidal bicategories, and I thought your paper was working in that context.
John Baez said:
For starters, am I correct that now you're using "autonomous" to mean what's also called "compact closed"? Mike Stay (for example) wrote a paper on compact closed symmetric monoidal bicategories, and I thought your paper was working in that context.
Oh, I think autonomous is probably what Mike Stay called compact. I got the term from Day-Street Monoidal Bicategories and Hopf Algebroids, and it means that every object is dualizable (in the weak sense). Looking back at their paper now, I wonder if some or all of my lemmas are in there somewhere.
(I don't have any preference for the term autonomous; it's just what I wrote in the paper, so I'm using it here, but compact seems more catchy)
Okay, thanks! For some reason I forgot you used "autonomous" in the paper. Yes, Street has generally used that word where others use "compact".
You're right that a key thing I wanted, and want, to figure out is why A is invertible as a 0-cell [A] is invertible as a 1-cell.
Yeah; I think that's the hard part. Or, maybe difficulty is relative, but it's the part that is not quite as formal as the others.
So I will carefully read your proof sketch for this! Perhaps a "string diagram" proof is too much to hope for, but we might get a "purely equational" proof - i.e. a concrete construction of an inverse for [A] from an inverse for A, and vice versa, where we can check that the inverses work simply by manipulating equations. It looks like you're doing this, at least for one half of this .
Yeah, I think that's right. I didn't do the other direction here because at some point I thought it was pretty straightforward. But we can think about that too after this part.
Okay! It will take me a little while to do this... I'll get back to you here. Thanks again!
Re: compact closed vs autonomous, I think a compact closed (bi)category is always symmetric monoidal, but at least some of the papers by Day, Street, etc. use "autonomous" to mean a non-symmetric monoidal bicategory with both left and right duals.
Re: string diagrams, I know Bartlett has used a syntax for monoidal bicategories where the strings denote the objects and 1-cells as in a monoidal bicategory, and the 2-cells relate different "pages" of these diagrams. But a fully geometric syntax for monoidal bicategories would indeed involve surface diagrams. Street had some attempts in that direction in "Functorial calculus in monoidal bicategories". More recently the folks behind [[homotopy.io]] have a higher-dimensional syntax that can be manipulated and sliced in different directions.
Okay, I've been proving the Lemmas using surface diagrams, or more precisely movies of string diagrams. Right now I'm stuck on Lemma 2, but I feel my calculus is expressive enough that I should be able to prove it, so either I've made a mistake or I'm just not seeing some trick I can use. Often quitting, going to bed, and trying the next day is the solution to such problems.
However I think I see a way to prove the Key Step: if A is invertible as a 0-cell, then [A] is invertible as a 1-cell. My proof seems a bit different than Niles', though it may boil down to the same thing in the end. I'll try to explain it tomorrow, and see if it makes sense. It amounts to combining various facts I like.
Great! Here's hoping you get unstuck :) And if you have a simple direct proof, that's even better. It should be simple, but there seems to be a lot of notation clutter in my attempts. (Which, I guess, is one of the things that string/surface calculus should really help with.)
Let me try outlining my alternative argument. It requires a bunch of facts that themselves take work to check, but seem important in their own right (if true :upside_down:).
I'll assume we're in a compact closed bicategory; this is basically the same as your autonomous symmetric monoidal bicategory, with slight technical differences that are worth noting. A compact closed bicategory is a symmetric monoidal bicategory M where for every object A there exists a dual A*.
But let me explain: in any monoidal bicategory, a dual of an object A is an object B equipped with a unit
and counit
satisfying the usual zigzag identities up to isomorphism.
(In Definition 4.11 here Mike Stay uses specified isomorphisms, the zigzagurators, which are required to obey some identities called the 'swallowtail coherence laws'. However Nick Gurski has shown (after Definition 2.3 in Biequivalences in tricategories) that these additional laws, which he calls the 'horizontal cusp laws', can be assumed without loss of generality: if the zigzagurators don't obey these laws we can systematically improve them so that they do. So, I will drop these coherence laws and treat the existence of the zigzagurator isomorphisms as a property, rather than incorporating them as part of the structure of a dual object. See Nick's discussion!)
This concept of compact closed bicategory seems technically different from your concept of autonomous symmetric monoidal bicategory in that I'm taking the existence of a dual for each object as a property, while you seem to be incorporating a specific choice of a dual as part of the structure of an autonomous symmetric monoidal bicategory.
I think the extra flexibility of my approach may help me, but I believe it's "not a big deal" in the following sense:
Conjecture 1. Given two duals and of an object in a monoidal bicategory, there is a canonically defined equivalence between these duals, i.e. an equivalence compatible with the units and counits.
Sorry for the vagueness in this statement, but I realize that if I'm not careful I'll wind up writing a paper here. I'd rather just answer questions than fill in tons of details preemptively.
I'm calling this a Conjecture just to cover my ass; it's a bicategorical analogue of a well-known fact for monoidal categories, namely that any two duals of an object are canonically isomorphic. Probably someone has already proved this analogue somewhere. I'd like a reference!
I'll say an object is an inverse of an object in a symmetric monoidal bicategory is equivalent to the tensor unit . Here I'm using symmetry merely to avoid the need to separately say as well.
Next, I'll use this nice result of Nick Gurski, which again is a generalization of a better-known fact for monoidal categories:
Theorem 2. If is an inverse of some object in a symmetric monoidal bicategory, then is a dual of : that is, there exists a unit
and counit
obeying the zigzag identities up to isomorphism. Moreover and are equivalences.
The proof of this is Section 3 of Biequivalences in tricategories: since we know and we can pick equivalences and then systematically improve them so that they obey the zigzag identities up to isomorphism.
I hadn't expected these preliminaries to be so long, but if you accept these things I believe it's easy to show
Key Step. An object in a symmetric monoidal bicategory has an inverse iff for some dual of the unit is an equivalence. In this case is an inverse of .
Proof. Suppose has an inverse . Then by Theorem 2, is a dual of and the unit is a equivalence.
Suppose for some dual of the unit is an equivalence. Then so is an inverse of . :black_large_square:
I think this proof of the key step is sufficiently satisfying to justify the longwinded methodological preliminaries!
In the same way we easily get another of @Niles Johnson's nice results:
Nice Result. An object in a symmetric monoidal bicategory has an inverse iff for some dual of the counit is an equivalence. In this case is an inverse of .
This is nice because in our motivating example - the bicategory of algebras, bimodules and bimodule homomorphisms - the unit is an equivalence iff is central and separable, while is an equivalence iff has two other nice properties:
John Baez said:
Let me try outlining my alternative argument...
Great! I'm glad you mentioned that paper of Nick's. This is not the first time I've thought that I would have a better grasp on the things I'm trying to do if I understood that paper a lot more. I think I see some ways to connect our two versions, so I'll write that because I found it clarifying.
I agree your Conjecture 1 has got to be correct, and I'm not really worried about the property/structure distinction. I often have the feeling that I better understand what I'm actually doing in the structured version, but that's probably more a matter of taste and habit than anything else.
Reading your proof, I was confused because I thought what I called was missing, but now I realize what I called is what you called , or . Then the thing I didn't give notation for, and said we wouldn't need ( with the -module structure on the other side) is what you called or .
I used my Lemma 1 to get , where the equivalences are symmetries that rearrange the , , , and . A dual version would give . (I'm skipping all the symmetry stuff because, as you said, it starts feeling like one is writing too much!)
At some point earlier you asked about a specific formula for the inverse of . Here's what I think it is in both notations, where I'm writing and denotes a symmetry equivalence.
or (with a different symmetry )
So, in this formula, the inverse is basically made from and .
From this point of view, I guess the Key Step seems to be saying that is a pair of inverse equivalences if and only if both and are such. Is that really right?! It seems a bit surprising, but I guess the point is that (waving hands and squinting) we have things like , and similarly for .
(I'm probably slipping back into my "structured" way of thinking here, but hopefully you get the idea ;)
Oh, I just realized you had been writing etc. where I wrote ; I meant to use the stars but I forgot!
Yes, I wrote just because that's a common name for duals and quicker than to type than op, and yes, I wrote for your [A], maybe because I was not wanting to suggest there's a single chosen such morphism given A.
At some point in the past I was confused by * because there are duals at two different levels here (algebras/objects v.s. modules/1-cells). [Edit: I've just realized that in addition to being a bit silly, the question I had here is not entirely well-formed, so let's just ignore it.]
Yes, I sort of like your use of to mean the unit object and to mean the dual of an object. When I first saw that I thought it was a clever trick to get a paper on symmetric monoidal bicategories published in a traditional algebra journal. :upside_down: But it's true, there are two levels of dual here so maybe it's confusing to use for both. Back when I writing a lot about -categories with duals I decided it was hopeless to make up a new kind of star for each level of duality. But with just two maybe I should do this.
Haha, well at that time I was trying harder to get traditional algebraists to be interested in my work. That was successful in at least one sense (I was told about it after being hired as a postdoc), but the paper didn't make it to an algebra journal.
Regarding notation, I'd probably lean more in the direction of using * at all levels now, but that's provided I can distinguish between an object, it's unit 1-cell, and the related unit we've called . In the more traditional algebra literature, those are all called A :/
True, though some algebraists at least use to mean a ring regarded as a left module of itself, and and to mean two other things.
When category theorists get too tired to talk about math they talk about notation. This morning I figured out a nice proof of the Key Step but now I'm just talking about notations for bimodules. :upside_down:
I don't know if this is relevant, but there's a new paper on the arXiv by Coquand, Lombardi, and Neuwirth called Constructive Remarks on Azumaya Algebra. The abstract says:
We study etale topology and the notion of Azumaya algebra over a commutative ring constructively. As an application of the syntactic version of Barr's Theorem, we show the equivalence between two definitions of Azumaya algebra.
Oh, cool; I'll have to check it out
Nice, thanks! Though I'm more of a destructive mathematician myself.