You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
In a simplicial set, if and are degenerate simplices of the same nondegenerate simplex , is there a 'smallest' degenerate simplex that is a degeneracy of both and , where is smaller than iff is a degeneracy of ? I feel like this is true but I'm struggling to come up with a straightforward proof...
I think this is false.
Consider a co-degeneracy map from the n-simplex to the 1-simplex. This is the same as an order-preserving surjective map from (0 < ... < n) to (0 < 1), which must send the first k elements to 0 and the next (n+1-k) to 1; so it is uniquely determined by a string .
Now you're asking whether given two co-degeneracy maps f, g: (n) -> (1) we can always find a co-degeneracy e: (m) -> (n) which equalises them, that is e;f = e;g.
I claim that we can't in general. Any co-degeneracy map can be factored into a sequence of “elementary collapses” (m+1) -> (m).
The way that precomposition with such an “elementary collapse” acts on the representation of a map (n) -> (1) as a bit-string is that it “duplicates” the bit in a certain position.
For f: (n) -> (1), you can consider the function p(f) that gives you the parity of (length of the string - number of 0s) in the bit-string representation of f.
Now you can see that, for all elementary collapses, you have that p(e;f) is the “negation” of p(f), because e either “adds a 0” or “adds a 1”, changing the parity.
By induction on the decomposition of a co-degeneracy into “elementary collapses”, you can see that for all co-degeneracies e: (m) -> (n), you have p(e;f) = p(e;g) if and only if p(f) = p(g).
So you just have to start from f, g with different parity and see that they can never be “unified”. For example, have f: (2) -> (1) be 001 and g: (2) -> (1) be 011.
So for example if in a simplicial set you have a non-degenerate 1-simplex , then the degenerate 2-simplices and do not have any common degeneracy.
Amar Hadzihasanovic said:
So you just have to start from f, g with different parity and see that they can never be “unified”. For example, have f: (2) -> (1) be 001 and g: (2) -> (1) be 011.
Isn't a degeneracy of both of them?
No, you can't get by pulling back and with the same map.
Which is what you would need to equalise and
...Ah wait I'm being stupid. That's not what you were actually asking.
And probably what I proved to be false can be shown to be false more trivially then what I did :D
Sorry if i wasn't clear, i don't think I need them to be degeneracies with the same map, just that like in this case, there exists a common degeneracy which is minimal, for example would be another common degeneracy but not minimal
I proved that there are no equalisers of co-degeneracies in the simplex category while I think what you are asking is essentially whether there are pullbacks of co-degeneracies in the simplex category.
I'll think about that later!
yes, i think that's what i meant.. alright, thanks Amar! :)
Well, I think there may be a simple proof: again see a co-degeneracy as being represented by a string , which you can also just see as a list of positive numbers, corresponding to “ sends the first elements to 0, the next to 1, etc.”.
(Here )
Then given , I claim the “smallest unifier” is the function given by the list .
I think that it shouldn't be too hard to show that this works...
I did not want to assume that the domain of and must be the same (should have said that earlier, sorry!)
Oh sorry I shouldn't have assumed f and g have the same domain either, I think the solution works the same
The only effect of having different domains is that and will be different!
thanks a lot, Amar :)
Amar Hadzihasanovic said:
I proved that there are no equalisers of co-degeneracies in the simplex category while I think what you are asking is essentially whether there are pullbacks of co-degeneracies in the simplex category.
what is really the correct way to phrase this? The pullback is actually happening in simplicial sets, but we want the cone point to be in the image of the Yoneda embedding? Or can we say the pullback is happening in the simplex category since the Yoneda embedding preserves & reflects limits?If so, can we prove this in a more abstract way, by just citing that the simplex category has all limits, or at least pullbacks (if that is true?)
I guess I was a bit imprecise; I think the statement is that there are pullbacks in the category of simplices & co-degeneracy maps.
We can tell that these are not pullbacks in the simplex category (including co-faces) because otherwise they would be preserved by the Yoneda embedding, but they are certainly not pullbacks in the category of simplicial sets.
Mmm maybe that's not right either. The “unification” as I described it would not really be unique in general... it's probably something weaker than a pullback...
Ok, I think I see what the correct statement is -- it's a bit weaker than the existence of pullbacks
Let be the category of simplices and co-degeneracy maps; equivalently, this is the category whose
For each , we consider the poset whose
This is the poset reflection of the slice category .
Claim: for all , the poset has binary meets; that is, for all , there is a “greatest” that factors through and , in the sense that
(This would be implied by having pullbacks, which is the same as having products for all , but it is strictly weaker, and in fact the stronger statement does not hold).
Proof: given and , represent them as sequences and with and , with the interpretation that I gave above ( sends the first elements to , the next to , etc).
Let correspond to the sequence , where .
Then factors through (possibly non-uniquely): take any sequence of surjective maps , and concatenate them together to get a surjective map such that .
Similarly, factors through (possibly non-uniquely).
Let be any other map that factors through both and , and is represented by the sequence .
Then it is straightforward to see that and for all (this is essentially the fact that the size of inverse images of an element can only increase by precomposition with a surjective map)
It follows that for all . Then taking any sequence of surjective maps and concatenating them together, we get a map such that , and that completes the proof.
So what follows is that if and are degenerate simplices coming from the same simplex, is the “smallest unifier” in this sense: if is a degeneracy of both and , then it is a degeneracy of .
Thank you so much, Amar, this is all so helpful. I see your point about nonuniqueness meaning this is not a pullback.
Regarding the sequence notation, should it be that instead of ? E.g. in your original example, if is , then and ?
(If you don't mind I'll acknowledge your support with this in my thesis.)
Ah yes, sure, you should increase all those by 1.