You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
oo, @Nicholas Scheel , I’ve thought about these a bit too! If I remember what I worked out a little while back it’s possible to characterize the interactions between sets of things that monoid elements act like identities towards, and the sets of things which they absorb...or something :P actually, I’m not sure I ever finished dealing with them, now that I think about it! :D
(in the case where you consider the almost-identities (that is, they [either absorb or are absorbed by] everything) in a commutative monoid, I’m preeeeetty sure they form a total order, right? as in your intuition of “layers”... is there something analogous for noncommutative monoids, I wonder?)
Can we prove it? Let a
and b
be two distinct almost-identities in a commutative (sub)monoid. Then either a
absorbs b
(a > b
), in which case ab = a
, or a
is absorbed by b
(a < b
), in which case ab = b
(trichotomy). Due to commutativity, if a
absorbs b
, then b
is absorbed by a
, and vice-versa, so it is anti-symmetric or something. Just need transitivity … a < b < c
so ab = b
and bc = c
so ac = a(bc) = (ab)c = bc = c
. Looks legit to me :)
I'm not sure how we would define almost-identities in the non-commutative case. If they have to treat all elements equally, then they might as well be in the center of the monoid, so we can use the original definition. I'm not sure otherwise, thoughts?
mm, true!! Maybe it would be interesting to separate the sets of “left-absorbed” and “right-absorbed” elements? (So, it would still absorb or be absorbed by everything—but whether it’s absorbed by or absorbs a given element is allowed to depend on which side we compose it on!)
I’m not sure if that’s consistent with associativity, though!
Hmm, it’s only allowed to vary from side to side for idempotent elements, at most, I think. Consider b an almost-identity varying from side to side for a: a(ba) = ab = a
, (ab)a = aa
Oh that's really interesting, so if there exists a non-idempotent element, then it cannot vary from side to side?
@T Murrills thought I would move our discussion to a new thread. For reference, this is what I originally said:
I was just thinking the other day that a lot of monoids have layers of elements that are identities or “almost-identities”, and also absorbing elements or almost-absorbing elements. E.g. m <> e = m (identity), and m <> e1 = m for all m != e (almost identity).
I think the case of an idempotent monoid is potentially still interesting, though, especially because a monoid generated from just these elements is idempotent.
yeah! So, I scrolled allll the way back in my tumblr drafts for my math blog to find this, and here’s the part of it I didn’t remember (looks like I didn’t get the idempotent bit, though!)
at the very least it suggests a notation!
(I called them “pseudoidentities”)
So like. We have this weird “double poset” structure? Like, there’s one poset for =», and one poset for =«. And certain interactions between their upsets/downsets that I didn’t get around to figuring out! We can define these relations on the whole monoid as they’re essentially “absorbs on the right” or “absorbs on the left”. Almost-identities are the ones that act as “bottlenecks” for both partial orders: everything is either above or below them
(I don’t like this notation a whole lot, so feel free to suggest another 😅)
Wait. That’s not a poset...
T Murrills said:
Hmm, it’s only allowed to vary from side to side for idempotent elements, at most, I think. Consider b an almost-identity varying from side to side for a:
a(ba) = ab = a
,(ab)a = aa
The definition you previously gave already forces "almost identities" to be idempotents :slight_smile:
Every idempotent defines a left, right and two-sided ideal; these are precisely the elements that absorb on the right, left and both sides respectively.
Morgan Rogers said:
The definition you previously gave already forces "almost identities" to be idempotents :slight_smile:
Right, we were talking about a general a : M
, not just the almost-identity elements.
One of the other streams brought up meadows, and it turns out this same kind of idempotent structure shows up and is useful in that setting: https://arxiv.org/pdf/0903.1196v1.pdf (section 3)
Lol, I literally had this open in a tab right now :heart:
I don't understand why their base ring is taken to be commutative tho. I guess they need it in the proofs? So I guess skew-fields are not meadows?
Right before the conclusion they say “every finite skew meadow is commutative”, which is a pretty nice result.
This seems a generalization of Wedderburn theorem, but it's strange cose in def. 2.1 meadows are assumed to be always commutative
Oh, now I see, they define skew-meadows in section 4
Meadows seem like a nicer class of rings to work with than fields, cool!
Their Definition 3.11 really grates on me, though; it makes it pretty obvious that they should have chosen a different name for the complementary elements than inverses...
Nicholas Scheel said:
One of the other streams brought up meadows, and it turns out this same kind of idempotent structure shows up and is useful in that setting: https://arxiv.org/pdf/0903.1196v1.pdf (section 3)
re this, were you talking about the fact that we can put an order structure on the idempotents in a commutative monoid?