You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
@John Baez and I want to determine conditions on which are necessary or sufficient for to have certain topos-theoretic properties: logical, locally cartesian closed, etc.
Let's start with the simplest, logical. As I understand, these are rare because they are so nice. What are useful necessary or sufficient conditions on for to be logical?
Is it just a coincidence that someone asked the same question for local cartesian closure on MathOverflow just an hour ago?
that is quite a coincidence. I'm not sure who that is
moving this to #theory: topos theory
This topic was moved here from #theory: category theory > morphisms of presheaf toposes by Christian Williams
I'm seeing one theorem which shows how special logical functors are: The Elephant A.2.3.8
so, a logical functor with a left adjoint that preserves pullbacks must be of the form "pullback along a morphism in a topos"
that's a big restriction.
if is cartesian, then the left adjoint of is cartesian. then if is logical, this theorem implies that it is actually an equivalence.
so, basically we can't expect inverse image functors of presheaf toposes to be logical.
but we don't have to focus the conversation only on ; we can also consider the extensions and .
from the topic on type theory of a topos, we made some progress toward if is cartesian closed then might be as well - subject to some condition of finitude
of course demanding any functor to be logical is very strict, so we can also ask for "sublogical" or "subclosed", where the canonical morphisms are not isomorphisms but just monic.
in general, this is a topic for conditions on giving various properties of , , and .
You could look at Corollaries 4.56 and 4.58 of Caramello's denseness conditions paper; these give conditions for the essential gm induced by to be locally connected, or equivalently for to be locally cartesian closed. The conditions are very fiddly, but more importantly don't appear to bear much resemblance to your situation.
It might be helpful to know that @Riccardo Zanfa and I have worked out that the first condition of Corollary 4.56 there can be reduced to the necessary and sufficient condition given by Johnstone for the induced geometric morphism to be open (equivalently, for to be sublogical) in C3.1.3 of the Elephant.
All this is a bit hard for me to understand. Are there any nice easy examples of functors such that is a logical morphism?
Any nice examples where and are finite categories, for example?
@John Baez Did you mean ? If so, I think we could potentially get some examples by looking at the relationship between and .
In particular, the codomain functor (which is logical) is the inverse image part of the essential geometric morphism determined by a functor .
But this logical functor is just another one of those slice examples... That is, you can reconstruct as the slice of over a certain representable subterminal object. This is the "generic" case of Artin gluing...
Yeah, I meant .
Thanks for the example! Here are some followup questions:
1) So the functor sending to has the property that is logical? Just checking.
2) Is it correct that the functor sending to does not have the property that is logical?
3) Is the only functor for which is logical the one mapping to ?
I have some vague intuition about this involving the concept of "time to truth" mentioned in Mac Lane and Moerdijk's discussion of these sorts of presheaf categories. They consider presheaves on where "the final truth is never known", but in the example categories I just mentioned, "the full truth is known on the last day" - sort of like Judgement Day in the bible.
I am likely to get some things backwards as soon as I start talking about indices, but it is true that one of those inverse image functors is the codomain functor (and therefore clearly logical), but the other one is the domain functor (which is not logical). These correspond to the generic open and closed immersions of topoi respectively...
Indeed, I probably got everything backwards due to the op in the definition of presheaves.
(I bet you got it forwards! But I don't want to claim it, becuase I always screw myself that way :laughing: )
Okay, well the invariant formulation of my question 3) is: does just one of the functors from the terminal category to induce a logical functor between presheaf categories, via pullback?
That's my conjecture: only one of them does.
i think there are more..
John Baez said:
All this is a bit hard for me to understand. Are there any nice easy examples of functors such that is a logical morphism?
Yes; take to be any discrete fibration. This identifies with the slice of over the corresponding presheaf, and the essential geometric morphism is the canonical one, whose leftmost adjoint is the forgetful functor, and whose inverse image is logical.
We precisely get the localic geometric morphisms into with logical inverse image this way.
John Baez said:
Thanks for the example! Here are some followup questions:
1) So the functor sending to has the property that is logical? Just checking.
2) Is it correct that the functor sending to does not have the property that is logical?
3) Is the only functor for which is logical the one mapping to ?
Since all of these examples are faithful functors, so induce localic essential geometric morphisms, we can see that they induce geometric morphisms with logical inverse image if and only if they are discrete fibrations, which is false in the first case (there is no lifting of the morphism ), true in the second case (so Jonathan did indeed get these mixed up), and true in the final case if and only if maps to .
Morgan Rogers (he/him) said:
John Baez said:
All this is a bit hard for me to understand. Are there any nice easy examples of functors such that is a logical morphism?
Yes; take to be any discrete fibration.
Great! That gives me a large supply of of examples I can try to understand in detail.
And you're saying that a faithful induces a logical morphism only if is a discrete fibration! That's great too, since together these facts settle questions like 1)-3).
Yep! For another supply of examples, you can take and to be groups; any group homomorphism is a functor which turns out to induce an atomic geometric morphism (i.e. one with logical inverse image). The geometric morphism is (hyper)connected if and only if the morphism is surjective, and localic if and only if the morphism is injective, which is pleasant.
Great - I like presheaves on groups, aka G-sets, because I'm basically an old-fashioned mathematician who likes stuff like G-sets and representations of groups and such.
I should also refer @Christian Williams to the fact that the direct image of a geometric morphism is cartesian closed or sublogical if and only if the geometric morphism is an inclusion, cf A4.2.9 and C3.1.8 in the Elephant, and the direct image functor is logical if and only if the morphism is an equivalence, so that's something of a dead end.
However, as I mentioned in previous discussion, there is a reasonable chance of the left adjoint which you're calling of having nice properties in the situations you're interested in.
Morgan Rogers (he/him) said:
You could look at Corollaries 4.56 and 4.58 of Caramello's denseness conditions paper; these give conditions for the essential gm induced by to be locally connected, or equivalently for to be locally cartesian closed. The conditions are very fiddly, but more importantly don't appear to bear much resemblance to your situation.
It might be helpful to know that Riccardo Zanfa and I have worked out that the first condition of Corollary 4.56 there can be reduced to the necessary and sufficient condition given by Johnstone for the induced geometric morphism to be open (equivalently, for to be sublogical) in C3.1.3 of the Elephant.
yes, you mentioned this before, thanks. it's very good to know that fibrations are sufficient for their inverse to be LCC. good to hear that you've made new progress in this area too!
Morgan Rogers (he/him) said:
I should also refer Christian Williams to the fact that the direct image of a geometric morphism is cartesian closed or sublogical if and only if the geometric morphism is an inclusion, cf A4.2.9 and C3.1.8 in the Elephant, and the direct image functor is logical if and only if the morphism is an equivalence
okay, I see the first fact in the book. how are you getting the second? I thought "logical iff equivalence" was only if it had a cartesian left adjoint
Direct image functors of geometric morphisms do have cartesian left adjoints (don't forget that that's what the right adjoint is called!)
"that that's what" is one of those freaky English constructions...
oh yes of course, thanks
so there isn't much hope for to be logical, fine. I'll think about those weakenings involving inclusions. right now the main thing I'll think about is conditions on for to be locally cartesian closed.
No, there's not much hope for to be logical.
Am I confused here?
I thought we'd just seen a bunch of fun examples where is logical.
yeah, sorry I was mixed up about something. those F* are logical, so they must not have cartesian left adjoints, because otherwise as Morgan says they would be equivalences.