You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Is it really ok to ask basic questions here? Let me try...
Suppose that we have a topos with a (Lawvere-Tierney) topology . Then for any subobject in it we can construct its closure by building its characteristic arrow , composing it with , and pulling back the arrow along , as in the diagram below.
``Everybody knows'' that we will then have , but I realized that I never knew the details of this, and I'm trying to fill the gaps. I'm trying to find an explicit construction for the monic and I'm failing miserably... Anyone knows how to do that? This is theorem 21.1 of McLarty's "Elementary Categories, Elementary Toposes", but his proof is too terse for me...
@Eduardo Ochs you do have , so there should be a commuting square with along the top, on the left, along the bottom, and on the right. Then I think the universal property of as a pullback gives , no?
More simply, take your diagram, add the identity arrow from 1 to 1, and then apply the pullback's universal property!
Ahaaa! Beatiful! Thanks!!!
Here is the finished version:
That's a nice neat write-up :heart_eyes:
Hi, another question... I am working in toposes of the form , where is a finite poset, and I am in a situation in which for any two subobjects and of 1 in the topos obeying the closure of the monic is easy to calculate; to be more precise, closures of these subobjects can be calculated using the operations in the paper Planar Heyting Algebras for Children 2 (PDF here), and so they are easy to visualize.
I want to prove that for any monic in that topos its closure, , is equal to the union of things that are easy to calculate and to visualize, in the following sense...
I know how to express the object as a union of representables. Formally, this "...as a union of representables" is a pair made of an index set and a family of monics, , such that each is a (representable) subobject of 1, and . And for each I can form a diagram like this:
Is it possible to prove that ? I am still struggling with the details on Lawvere-Tierney Topologies in the first pages about them in each of a handful of books... I haven't reached yet the parts in which the `'s interact with unions of subobjects -- so brief hints like "look at page xxx in book yyy" are probably going to be very useful.
Thanks in advance!!!
Update: I think I found an argument that works! Treating all entities from here on as elements of , we have: , , ; so ...
It seems to me that the argument in your Update uses these facts appropriately, so it works!
Hi all, especially @David Michael Roberts and @[Mod] Morgan Rogers,
I finished writing down my notes on topologies and closure operators - they are here: http://angg.twu.net/math-b.html#clops-and-tops - but I added a section that is still unfinished on something that I guess that is known, but I can't find it in the literature... namely, that for toposes of the form , where this is a finite poset, the operation that takes a closure operator on the topos and restricts it to is a bijection between topologies and operations on the Heyting Algebra of the truth-values of the topos that obey and ...
Any pointers would be very welcome! =)
Sounds like the corresponding Lawvere-Tierney topology to me.
Corresponding to what?...
Every closure operator has a corresponding Lawvere-Tierney topology and vice-versa, but these operators on the Heyting Algebra of truth-values are a third thing. I am not sure if I understood you correctly, though.
The corresponding closure operator on is called a nucleus. For localic Grothendieck toposes, Lawvere–Tierney topologies (equivalently, Grothendieck topologies on ) correspond bijectively to nuclei on the frame . This is also the case here, because is a localic topos for any poset.
In the case where is a finite poset, these correspond precisely to the subsets of .
In "Grothendieck topologies on a poset" by @Bert Lindenhovius it is shown that more generally the Grothendieck topologies on any Artinian poset correspond to the subsets of .
As a reference:
In Maclane–Moerdijk, "Sheaves in Geometry and Logic", IX.5, Corollary 6, it is shown that nuclei on a locale correspond to Lawvere–Tierney topologies on the topos .
Wow!!!! Thanks!!!!!! =) =) =)
Sorry, just saying "Lawvere-Tierney topology" admittedly wasn't so helpful. What I was trying to say was that the LT topology is a mapping , and in a presheaf topos the global elements of , are precisely the subterminal objects, which is to say the truth values of the topos, so the nucleus is given by .
I understand the confusion, I routinely call nuclei LT-topologies and viceversa :laughing:
It should generally be harmless to confuse the two right?
Since they’re both modal operators on the truth values of the category - just one is internal and one is external
Yeah, I guess
And when the category is a topos, an external operator will internalise to an internal one (like all the other logic which internalises)
I wouldn't use the term Lawvere-Tierney topology if the category wasn't a topos. Maybe one should say 'internal nucleus'
I think Johnstone calls Lawvere-Tierney topologies ‘local operators’
I don’t really see the problem with using the same name for both since that’s what happens with unions, intersections, quantifiers, etc
Ok but 'topology' doesn't really make sense outside a topos. Of course the two notions are the same, syntactically speaking, but LT topology has a different attitude.
Fawzi Hreiki said:
It should generally be harmless to confuse the two right?
For localic toposes, it's more or less the same thing. For general Grothendieck toposes, each Lawvere–Tierney topology defines a nucleus on as @[Mod] Morgan Rogers says, but different Lawvere–Tierney topologies can induce the same nucleus on . This is maybe why the terminology 'nucleus' is used for frames and the terminology 'Lawvere–Tierney topology' only for toposes. I agree that they are very related concepts.
Indeed, in an extreme case, like the topos of presheaves on a monoid, all non-degenerate topologies induce the same nucleus :upside_down:
It's good you are writing this in detail! I recently finished supervising a student who was proving some category theoretic stuff in full detail, and it honestly surprised me how much I would have left out if I were writing it myself. Unfortunately I don't know of anything in the literature about this, sorry about that.