You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Hello all, here's the stream for David's talk, "Polynomial functors II: Seven wonders of the composition product".
Youtube live stream:
https://youtu.be/bLVHO5LxUY0
Zoom meeting:
https://mit.zoom.us/j/280120646
Meeting ID: 280 120 646
The slides are available, here: http://math.mit.edu/~dspivak/informatics/talks/poly2_wondersMIT2020.pdf
A lot of the wonderful properties of Poly seems to be 'shared' with Species (and also of other categories from concurrency theory based on [Inj, Set] ). I've been slowly exploring what makes all those monoidal structures on [A, B] work, as a way to understand how they all fit together.
@Jacques Carette can you name some of the other categories from concurrency theory of which you are thinking? :-)
I'm mainly thinking of the functor category I mentioned, from (finite sets + injections) to Set. It seems to be quite pervasive.
Is this the same thing as the schanuel topos (https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/Schanuel+topos)? I know of a variety of uses in computer science, but I'm sure which concurrency theory applications you're thinking of?
The Schanuel topos is a subcategory of [Inj, Set], where the functors are pullback-preserving.
I'll dig up some references - I can't immediately find good ones.
Hello all! We start in 10 minutes.
30 seconds!
Do you have a link?
Never mind!
What does Poly not have that Set has?
Can you go over what morphisms in poly are again?
(in my head it's a generalization of "divides" for classic polynomials but I'm not sure that's right)
Okay thanks
I first encountered Inj in A fully abstract model for the Pi-calculus.
The discussion of symmetry and lists reminds me of this old post on combinatorics from brent which is about ordered vs. unordered gadgets. List is the sum over ordered n-tuples, so one also may want to consider sets as the sum over unordered n-tuples: https://byorgey.wordpress.com/2012/08/24/unordered-tuples-and-type-algebra/
https://www.cis.upenn.edu/~sweirich/papers/yorgey-thesis.pdf
Is there an expectation that all of this structure should also arise in the context of general polynomial functors on locally cartesian-closed categories, or did anything described in the talk particularly rely on Set?
I missed the talk but the slides are nice, thanks! The definition of cofunctor is reminiscent of cartesian liftings in a fibration. Can a cofunctor be identified with something like a span of functors in which the first leg is a discrete opfibration and the second leg is bijective on objects?
@Mike Shulman: a similar characterisation of (internal) cofunctors is given in Clarke's Internal Lenses as Functors and Cofunctors.
Not just similar but identical! Thanks.
The best kind of similar :big_smile:
Mike Shulman said:
Can a cofunctor be identified with something like a span of functors in which the first leg is a discrete opfibration and the second leg is bijective on objects?
That's right. One interesting thing about this is that this kind of span is precisely those that induce coalgebra homomorphisms on the incidence coalgebras. It works the same for decomposition spaces more generally than category objects, but then the bijective-on-objects should be
bijective on objects and inner Kan fibration. (For category objects the inner-Kan-fibration condition is automatic.)
Nathanael Arkor said:
Is there an expectation that all of this structure should also arise in the context of general polynomial functors on locally cartesian-closed categories, or did anything described in the talk particularly rely on Set?
Yes, it should be exactly the same in the general case.
Nathanael Arkor said:
A similar characterisation of (internal) cofunctors is given in Clarke's Internal Lenses as Functors and Cofunctors.
Thanks, this is very nice.
Joachim Kock said:
this kind of span is precisely those that induce coalgebra homomorphisms on the incidence coalgebras
Sorry, I was too fast: not exactly the same, but an important example of. To get coalgebra homomorphisms, it is enough for the forward leg to be culf. Discrete opfibration is an example of that.
What does culf mean?
Todd Trimble said:
What does culf mean?
Sorry --- it's for conservative and unique-lifting-of-factorisations, also known as discrete Conduché fibration. (In higher settings, the discrete-Conduché-fibration terminology becomes a bit akward, because discreteness is no longer appropriate (and in any case these things were discovered before Conduché.) Actually 'conservative' is implied by 'ulf' for categories, but in more general simplicial situations, it is nice to have it as a separate condition.
Hey all, here's the permanent video:
https://youtu.be/3AOGDTr1zrY
Mike Shulman said:
The definition of cofunctor is reminiscent of cartesian liftings in a fibration.
The link between cofunctors and opcartesian lifts for split opfibrations is the topic of my recent preprint: Internal split opfibrations and cofunctors
I didn't notice before, this is the Topos Institute youtube channel, a sign of the future
CORRECTION
In my comment after David's talk, I said there is a fifth monoidal structure, namely the Hadamard product (which for power series is ). Unfortunately it's not true for the whole category David talks about. The Hadamard product is functorial only in cartesian natural transformations, not in general ones :-(
For example: we have ; there is a map (induced by ); and we have . But there is no map from to .
Sorry about the mistake. (I am too used to working only with cartesian natural transformations, which are the ones relevant for operad theory).
That actually resolves a difficulty I was having yesterday defining the Hadamard product; I thought I must be missing something because I couldn't get it to work. Thank you for clarifying!
@Jacques Carette did you manage to dig up the further monoidal product you mentioned in the questions at the end of the talk?
EDIT: Ah, I see, that's what the thesis link was for.
Right, that link was thrown there live, without explanation. The monoidal structure is called the 'arithmetic product' by those who first pointed it out (Maia and Mendez - https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0012365X07007960) from 2008. The link to Brent's thesis is because he explains it nicely. @Joachim Kock said that this might also be the Dirichlet product?
I've also found the set of slides https://www.slideshare.net/vieplivee/mit-0309-nopause that introduces the relation with a product on graphs to be quite interesting.
The arithmetic product of species is also called the Dirichlet product, yes.
Did anyone work out if that restricts to Poly in a nice way? It certainly doesn't in the finitary world, but we have that much more flexibility here.
David described the Dirichlet product of polynomials in his talk (the tensor product ).
Oh my mistake, I was looking at the Dirichlet convolution, which from its unit I gather is a distinct concept, and isn't even related to polynomials...
By the way, I listed the 5 main monoidal structures on species on the nLab.
Does anyone know why Poly is the subcategory of [Set,Set] spanned by functors that preserve connected limits?
Polynomial functors and polynomial monads gives proofs/references for the equivalence of this characterisation with others in Section 1.18.
If a functor preserves connected limits and the terminal, then it preserves all limits. So if preserves connected limits, then the evident induced functor , taking to , preserves all limits. Then, pulling back along each element gives a functor which preserves limits, hence is representable, say a functor . In the end we get .
Thanks @Todd Trimble. Why does the pullback preserve limits? Why must a set functor preserving limits be representable?
Nathanael Arkor asked:
Is there an expectation that all of this structure should also arise in the context of general polynomial functors on locally cartesian-closed categories, or did anything described in the talk particularly rely on Set?
and I replied
Yes, it should be exactly the same in the general case.
It was silly of me to answer like this.
There are several subtleties or even problems, when passing from Set to more general locally cartesian categories: for example sometimes you have to demand that some objects are discrete/complemented/decidable; you have to make more careful distinction between internal sums and external sums; you generally have to assume natural transformations are strong (that's automatic in Set). Altogether I think my answer was bad.
I have already made several comments that were too fast :-( I should take a break.
Joshua Meyers said:
Thanks Todd Trimble. Why does the pullback preserve limits? Why must a set functor preserving limits be representable?
The functor preserves limits because it has a left adjoint, namely the functor which sends a set to the map .
If a functor preserves limits, then it has a left adjoint by the special adjoint functor theorem, hence , which says that is representable.