You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
For which toposes is the category of its points small?
The category of points of a localic topos is always (essentially) small. Beyond that I don't know a general answer; e.g. I wouldn't expect there to be any clean criterion for which geometric theories have only a small number of isomorphism classes of models in Set.
Thank you very much!
My motivation for the question was that I wanted to find a left inverse of the inclusion of sober spaces into toposes. My idea was to send a topos to the space given by the points of and the open subtoposes of . But since the points of need not form a set, this isn't well-defined.
So is it the cases that the inclusion of sober spaces into toposes does not have a left inverse?
But how, then, would one categorically express that a sober space can be reconstructed from its topos of sheaves by considering its points? (Of course one can say that the inclusion is fully faithful, but having something like a left inverse would be slightly better.)
Also, does the inclusion of sober spaces into locales have a left inverse?
(By "inverse", I always mean "inverse up to natural isomorphism".)
_If_ you have a topos that comes from a sober space then you can perform the reconstruction you suggest.
Also, I don't know if the assignment is functorial, i.e., induces a continuous map for each topos morphism. Is it?
Yes, it is functorial, because you can pull back open subtoposes.
Any topos has a "localic reflection", obtained from the hyperconnected-localic factorization system. Thus, the inclusion of locales in toposes has a left inverse which is in fact a left adjoint. Similarly, the inclusion of sober spaces in locales has a left inverse that is a right adjoint, which takes the space of points. So combined, the inclusion of sober spaces in toposes also has a left inverse, though it is no longer an adjoint on either side.
Thanks!
@Mike Shulman Cool! How does this particular left inverse of the inclusion of sober spaces in toposes differ from ?
I don't know offhand, sorry.
Well, for one thing, taking the localic reflection first ensures that you get a small set of points.
Hi @Leopold Schlicht, something close to
is described in this paper by Caramello, Section 2.1.
If you take a set of points of the topos , then the topology on given by the open subtoposes is called the subterminal topology. If is a separating set of points, then is the localic reflection of .
For a monoid , points of are the same thing as flat left -sets. The topos does not have any open subtoposes (other than the empty topos and the topos itself), so the subterminal topology will be the indiscrete topology. If you then turn this into a sober space, you get just one point.
Thanks!
Mike Shulman said:
I wouldn't expect there to be any clean criterion for which geometric theories have only a small number of isomorphism classes of models in Set.
At least for first-order theories over a finite signature the following conditions are equivalent:
(3) implies (2) follows from the compactness theorem and (1) implies (3) follows from Löwenheim–Skolem.
I wonder what's true in geometric logic.
There can surely be infinitely many finite models?
Example? Note that I require the signature to be finite.
Ah okay, I'd missed that. In that case I agree, assuming also that the relations and operations in the signature have finite arity (much as this consequence of the compactness theorem is still counterintuitive to me!)
But restricting to finite signatures is rather unrepresentative for studying theories classified by toposes. After all, any infinite space has infinitely many points, and hence so does the topos of sheaves on that space, but not a large collection of points!
I believe there's a geometric theory of finite sets. It has one axiom
The signature is finite (one sort, no relations or operations), but it should have infinitely many finite models and no infinite models.
What's the meta-theory in which you write down that axiom? is surprisingly hard to axiomatize properly. [It's generated some nice papers for people who have tried.]
Any theory with a natural numbers object?
What's the problem with it?
I think @Jacques Carette's point is that …
is typically used as ad hoc notation for some form of iteration, but with unclear formal semantics.
Do you seriously think there is any ambiguity in what I wrote?
Of course if I were going to formalize it in a proof assistant I would have to define something formal by recursion, but in mathematics we write things like that all the time and no one objects.
I don't think there is any ambiguity; in geometric logic, you are able to express infinitary axioms, and it is clear what the axiom you wrote expands to.
@Nathanael Arkor Exactly. @Mike Shulman Mathematically? Most definitely not.
It's a different question about expressing these kinds of axioms in a finitary language.
But geometric logic is not a finitary language. That's the point.
The question, as I understood it, was whether a theory in geometric logic over a finite signature can have infinitely many models that are all finite. I think this theory shows that the answer to that question is yes. Are you wondering about a different question? Or objecting to that somehow?
My main point was to remark that to 'say' your one axiom formally assumes quite a lot of power in your ambient theory, even though it's mathematically obvious what it meant. A further point is that, if one scours the literature for occurrences of such 'mathematically obvious' notation, it turns out that the actual interpretation can often be significantly more subtle than it appears.
I possibly erred in attaching my comment to this particular thread, as the context (geometric logic) does indeed have enough power to say this, and thus I was being confusing.
Ok. I agree that infinitary language are quite powerful and subtle in general!
For example, when people use notation, it's not always clear if the case is allowed or not. In practice, both occur.
Well, that's just sloppy. (-:
Much more interesting is that there are cases where in notation, when there are multiple uses of in the same formula, there are cases where one can actually take to be negative and the result ends up being meaningful! This is the case for a number of block-matrix identities, for examples, but also other generalizations to situations with sums and its continuous counterpart, integrals.
This is getting quite far off from the subject of this thread.
Agreed.
Morgan Rogers (he/him) said:
But restricting to finite signatures is rather unrepresentative for studying theories classified by toposes.
Which toposes are classified by a geometric theory over a finite signature?
Mike Shulman said:
I believe there's a geometric theory of finite sets. It has one axiom
The signature is finite (one sort, no relations or operations), but it should have infinitely many finite models and no infinite models.
Alright. Probably Löwenheim–Skolem fails too for geometric logic.
@Jacques Carette Thanks for the comments. Interesting!