You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Hi,
I was wondering if there is a formal connection between limits in the categorical sense, and the "traditional" limits of function/sequence.
I get that the limit can be seen as a lower upper bound in case of ordered elements, but to me it seems like a specific case of limit.
@Vincent L See this.
thank you
diagonal functor is sending to ?
Yes.
I drew up some pictures of an adjunction with the diagonal functor a week ago on math stack exchange
thank you !
Vincent L said:
diagonal functor is sending to ?
I think the diagonal functor mentioned in the accepted answer on MO is more general, it implicitly depends on the indexing category. Here is how I define it in my (unfinished) notes ( is the category of functors from to ):
image.png
In their example, if you consider the functor and a filter , then is the constant functor that sends everything to .
thank you
was a bit confused because was from to .
and G wasn't really a product
I don't really understand " is a limit", as far as I understand it's a natural transformation, and a limit is a functor ?
or is it the natural transformation between the apex of the cone and the base ?
is just the constant diagram (i.e. functor) at . A cone is a natural transformation from a constant diagram to a diagram. The statement that is a limit means that is the universal cone.
thank for the clarification
This is all pretty well explained here https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/diagram
And the relationship to the more straightforward definition of limit as an object equipped with some maps such that ...
This is all pretty well explained here https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/diagram
And the relationship to the more straightforward definition of limit as an object equipped with some maps such that ...
I'm also interested in this question. I know that a link to the MathOverflow answer was posted, but there is this another answer here in the same question:
I am not completely satisfied by the accepted answer because the functor which characterizes the convergence of a filter depends on the limit. I therefore add another quite simple answer (written for sequences but this easily generalizes to filters and nets) to this old post...
So, I was wondering if there were any books/articles going a bit further on this topic. Do you people agree with the criticism posted above?
In the same MO post, someone suggested the following. Consider a category which is a poset on the natural numbers, i.e. , where there is a morphism between and if . Now, given a sequence of real numbers , make a functor , such that . One can then show that a cone in as an upper-bound, and the limit of would be the least upperbound.
So, I suppose that the colimit of would be the least lowerbound. Hence, would it be correct to say that if the cone category has a zero object, then the sequence has a limit, which would be such zero object?
The author that critiqued the given answer provided the following definition:
Let now be a sequence in some topological space . Then the limit of the contravariant functor assigning to the set is the set of all limit points of the sequence.
I think that this is a strong relation between analytical and functorial limits although it does not yet characterize convergence of sequences.
Unfortunately, the author states that this definition is still lacking.
(EDIT: I was confusing cones with cocones before, it is now fixed but my comment is less clear.)
A functor between two posets is the same thing as an order preserving functions (the condition that morphisms between and are taken to morphisms between and implies ). So your functor is a non-decreasing function from to , and the corresponding sequence is also non-decreasing.
A cocone under is an upper bound of the set , and the tip of the colimit cocone (it exists if and only that set has an upper bound --- that is usually an axiom put on in early analysis classes) is the least upper bound and the limit of the sequence (because the sequence is non-decreasing).
A cone over is a lower bound of the set , and the tip of the limit cone (it always exists) is which is guaranteed to be the greatest lower bound (because the sequence is non-decreasing).
(There is probably a better way to write this so that the categorical limit (and not the colimit) is the analytical limit, I leave this task to the reader.)
Right, for the inf of a non-increasing sequence you would want a colimit of a functor out of , but neither limit nor colimit recovers the analytic notion of convergence of a sequence.
Davi Sales Barreira said:
Hence, would it be correct to say that if the cone category has a zero object, then the sequence has a limit, which would be such zero object?
You are technically correct, but not morally so (I assume you write 'zero object' for an object that is both initial and terminal). The cocone category of never has a terminal object. A cocone over is simply a real number bigger than all , thus if is a cocone, then is a cocone, and there is no morphism of cocone from the latter to the former because . We conclude that is not terminal.
Therefore, after dualizing what I said (sorry for this step), we find that your statement "if the cone category has a zero object, then the sequence has a limit" is vacuously true.
It is extremely atypical for a cone category to have a zero object (but I don't have an intelligent explanation for why that is). What we are usually interested in is a terminal object in a cone category (i.e. a limit) or, dually, an initial object in a cocone category (i.e. a colimit).
Yeah, I've realized that the functor in I've talked about would only work for monotonic sequences, hence, the limit of would be the sup for the increasing sequence, and the colimit would be the inf for the decreasing sequence.
Davi Sales Barreira said:
The author that critiqued the given answer provided the following definition:
Let now be a sequence in some topological space . Then the limit of the contravariant functor assigning to the set is the set of all limit points of the sequence.
I think that this is a strong relation between analytical and functorial limits although it does not yet characterize convergence of sequences.Unfortunately, the author states that this definition is still lacking.
Now, what about this construction here.
I don't know about that construction, but the limit of a Cauchy sequence in a Lawvere metric space is an enriched-categorical limit. (And also a colimit, since it's an absolute limit.)