Category Theory
Zulip Server
Archive

You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.


Stream: learning: questions

Topic: left adjoint = right adjoint


view this post on Zulip Tim Hosgood (May 10 2021 at 00:09):

is there a name for an adjunction (LR)(L\dashv R) such that (LRL)(L\dashv R\dashv L) ?

(e.g. the functor F ⁣:IdemSetF\colon\mathsf{Idem}\to\mathsf{Set} given by F ⁣:(X,v){xXv(x)=x}F\colon (X,v)\mapsto\{x\in X\mid v(x)=x\} is right and left adjoint to the functor i ⁣:SetIdemi\colon\mathsf{Set}\to\mathsf{Idem} given by i ⁣:X(X,idX)i\colon X\mapsto(X,\mathrm{id}_X), where Idem\mathsf{Idem} is the category whose objects are pairs (X,v)(X,v) of sets XX and idempotents v ⁣:XXv\colon X\to X)

view this post on Zulip Tim Hosgood (May 10 2021 at 00:12):

as a fun bonus question, is it possible to have an adjunction (LR)(L\dashv R) such that (LRLR)(L\dashv R\dashv L\dashv R\dashv\ldots) for an arbitrary finite length?

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 00:23):

The way I read it, if LRLL\dashv R\dashv L, then LRLLR L \dashv R \dashv L \dashv L \dashv R \dashv \cdots forever.

To me LRLRLR L \dashv R \dashv L \dashv R \dashv L \dashv R \dashv \cdots just says

LL is left adjoint to RR and
RR is left adjoint to LL and
LL is left adjoint to RR and
RR is left adjoint to LL and ...

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 00:23):

and this gets to be old news pretty darn quick.

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 00:24):

It sounds like you must mean something else by it.

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 00:25):

Anyway, if LRL \vdash R and RLR \vdash L, I say we've got an ambidextrous adjunction.

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 00:30):

Btw, the nLab says an ambidextrous adjunction is one where LRL \vdash R and RLR \vdash L' and LLL \simeq L', but you can always improve such a situation to obtain RLR \vdash L.

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 00:32):

Any homomorphism between finite groups gives an ambidextrous adjunction between their categories of finite-dimensional representations, where the two functors involved are called "restriction" and "induction". This fact underlies what group theorists call "Frobenius reciprocity".

view this post on Zulip Tim Hosgood (May 10 2021 at 00:47):

John Baez said:

The way I read it, if LRLL\dashv R\dashv L, then LRLLR L \dashv R \dashv L \dashv L \dashv R \dashv \cdots forever.

To me LRLRLR L \dashv R \dashv L \dashv R \dashv L \dashv R \dashv \cdots just says

LL is left adjoint to RR and
RR is left adjoint to LL and
LL is left adjoint to RR and
RR is left adjoint to LL and ...

oh of course, sorry! I meant to ask the potentially more interesting (but less relevant) question of how long a chain of adjunctions (F1F2F3Fn)(F_1\dashv F_2\dashv F_3\dashv \ldots \dashv F_n) can be, and whether or not we have an easy example for all nn.

view this post on Zulip Tim Hosgood (May 10 2021 at 00:48):

John Baez said:

Anyway, if LRL \vdash R and RLR \vdash L, I say we've got an ambidextrous adjunction.

this is what I was looking for in my main question though, thank you!

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 01:03):

Tim Hosgood said:

oh of course, sorry! I meant to ask the potentially more interesting (but less relevant) question of how long a chain of adjunctions (F1F2F3Fn)(F_1\dashv F_2\dashv F_3\dashv \ldots \dashv F_n) can be, and whether or not we have an easy example for all nn.

Of course once you have an ambidextrous adjunction you have an example of F1F2F3FnF_1\dashv F_2\dashv F_3\dashv \ldots \dashv F_n for any n,n, so you must really be looking for a situation where F1F2F3FnF_1\dashv F_2\dashv F_3\dashv \ldots \dashv F_n but there does not exist Fn+1F_{n+1} with FnFn+1F_n \dashv F_{n+1}.

There's an nLab article about this:

Here's a fun example:

Take [n][n] to be a linearly ordered set with nn elements and take [n+1][n+1] to be a linearly ordered set with n+1n+1 elements. View them both as categories.

There are nn functors from [n+1][n+1] to [n][n] corresponding to order-preserving maps that are onto.

There are also n+1n+1 functors from [n][n] to [n+1][n+1] corresponding to order-preserving maps that are "almost onto": their image includes all but one of the elements of [n+1][n+1].

All these functors can be arranged into an adjoint string of length 2n+12n+1.

view this post on Zulip Joachim Kock (May 10 2021 at 02:52):

There is an interesting situation for compactly generated tensor triangulated categories: Balmer, Dell'Ambrogio and Sanders show that a tensor exact functor between such categories can be the leftmost functor in a string of either 3, 5 or infinitely many adjoints. There are always at least three, as follows readily by Brown representability. If there is a fourth adjoint functor, then we are in the situation of Grothendieck-Neeman duality, and in that case there is also a fifth. If there is a sixth, then we are in the situation of Wirthmüller isomorphism, which makes the adjoint functors repeat themselves infinitely.

view this post on Zulip Tim Hosgood (May 10 2021 at 12:41):

Joachim Kock said:

There is an interesting situation for compactly generated tensor triangulated categories: Balmer, Dell'Ambrogio and Sanders show that a tensor exact functor between such categories can be the leftmost functor in a string of either 3, 5 or infinitely many adjoints. There are always at least three, as follows readily by Brown representability. If there is a fourth adjoint functor, then we are in the situation of Grothendieck-Neeman duality, and in that case there is also a fifth. If there is a sixth, then we are in the situation of Wirthmüller isomorphism, which makes the adjoint functors repeat themselves infinitely.

this is a really interesting result! I love that it's either three, five, or infinity

view this post on Zulip Tim Hosgood (May 10 2021 at 12:42):

John Baez said:

Tim Hosgood said:

oh of course, sorry! I meant to ask the potentially more interesting (but less relevant) question of how long a chain of adjunctions (F1F2F3Fn)(F_1\dashv F_2\dashv F_3\dashv \ldots \dashv F_n) can be, and whether or not we have an easy example for all nn.

Here's a fun example:

Take [n][n] to be a linearly ordered set with nn elements and take [n+1][n+1] to be a linearly ordered set with n+1n+1 elements. View them both as categories.

There are nn functors from [n+1][n+1] to [n][n] corresponding to order-preserving maps that are onto.

There are also n+1n+1 functors from [n][n] to [n+1][n+1] corresponding to order-preserving maps that are "almost onto": their image includes all but one of the elements of [n+1][n+1].

All these functors can be arranged into an adjoint string of length 2n+12n+1.

huh, this is a very simplicial example, i'm shocked i hadn't seen this before! thanks :)

view this post on Zulip Fawzi Hreiki (May 10 2021 at 12:46):

In the framework of axiomatic cohesion, the inclusion of sets into spaces (as discrete spaces) has a left adjoint (connected components) and a right adjoint (points). When the category of spaces is a homotopy category, you have components = points (i.e. every component has exactly one point).

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (May 10 2021 at 14:20):

I don't think the right adjoint "points" exists when the category of spaces is a homotopy category: you can't isolate the "set of points" of a homotopy type.

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (May 10 2021 at 14:21):

There is an example from axiomatic cohesion though: the right adjoint "points" also often has a further right adjoint that equips each space with the codiscrete topology, and in some cases discrete = codiscrete, such as the category of parametrized spectra.

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 16:04):

Tim Hosgood said:

huh, this is a very simplicial example, i'm shocked i hadn't seen this before! thanks :)

Yes, this string of adjunctions consists of the face and degeneracy maps between simplices of neighboring dimension, but where we think of these simplices as totally ordered sets and thus categories.

view this post on Zulip John Baez (May 10 2021 at 16:06):

I don't know anything interesting that you can do with this string of adjunctions... like, something cool about simplicial sets that relies on it.

view this post on Zulip Tim Hosgood (May 10 2021 at 16:50):

yeah that’s what i’d like to know next!

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (May 10 2021 at 16:54):

I believe that the resulting "augmented simplex 2-category" is something like the free monoidal 2-category containing a lax-idempotent monoid. At least, something like this appears in Street's Fibrations in bicategories. But you should check it out and be sure before quoting me.

view this post on Zulip Tobias Fritz (May 10 2021 at 19:51):

I'm not sure if this is related, but there's also a fun string of adjoint functors relevant to homological algebra: if CC^\to is the arrow category of any category CC, then the identity-taking functor id:CC\mathsf{id} : C \to C^\to is part of a sequence of adjunctions

codiddom.\mathsf{cod} \dashv \mathsf{id} \dashv \mathsf{dom}.

Now if CC has an initial object 00, then there is a further left adjoint 0:CC0:C \to C^\to sending an object AA to the unique arrow 0A0 \to A. If CC has cokernels with respect to this initial object, then taking cokernels is a further left adjoint coker0\mathsf{coker} \dashv 0. And similarly if CC has a terminal object 11 and has kernels with respect to it, then we obtain a right adjoint and a right-right adjoint for dom\mathsf{dom}.

So if all of these things exist, then we have an adjoint string of length seven! It is

coker0codiddom1ker.\mathsf{coker} \dashv 0 \dashv \mathsf{cod} \dashv \mathsf{id} \dashv \mathsf{dom} \dashv 1 \dashv \mathsf{ker}.

At some point I was wondering whether one could develop a "synthetic" version of homological algebra based on this observation. But I'm not sure how interesting or useful it would be.

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (May 10 2021 at 23:48):

Note that that adjoint 7-tuple extends further in either direction if and only if the (\infty-)category is stable, in which case the chain is infinite. Moritz Rahn (nee Groth) and I remarked on the analogous fact for derivators in section 6 of Generalized stability for abstract homotopy theories. So you could regard such a structure as a formal context for stability, which is similar to homological algebra.

view this post on Zulip Tobias Fritz (May 11 2021 at 06:41):

Wow! I don't know the technical details of stable \infty-categories, but perhaps it's still possible to gain some intuition about that version of the statement? I understand that the \infty-version of the cokernel functor is the mapping cone functor. Am I interpreting your notation correctly in that its left adjoint would be the functor taking an object AA to the unique arrow ΩA0\Omega A \to 0? I feel like I should be able to complete the sentence "Mapping into a mapping cone is the same thing as ...", but right now I don't see it.

view this post on Zulip Matteo Capucci (he/him) (May 11 2021 at 10:02):

I remember reading once about a characterization of Set as a category whose Yoneda embedding fits into an adjoint string of length 7 5. I don't remember the details but I always found it very funny. Also I didn't know that length 7 adjoint strings were so common! Your example, Tobias, is really wonderful. It's odd I've never seen it mentioned anywhere.

view this post on Zulip Nathanael Arkor (May 11 2021 at 10:30):

I remember reading once about a characterization of Set as a category whose Yoneda embedding fits into an adjoint string of length 7.

Length 5: Rosebrugh–Wood's An Adjoint Characterization of the Category of Sets.

view this post on Zulip Matteo Capucci (he/him) (May 11 2021 at 11:59):

Thanks Nathanael :)

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (May 11 2021 at 15:36):

Tobias Fritz said:

Am I interpreting your notation correctly in that its left adjoint would be the functor taking an object AA to the unique arrow ΩA0\Omega A \to 0?

Yes, that's right. The crucial observation is that stably, the mapping cone is the suspension of the mapping cocone (fiber), and suspension is the inverse of loops. So given f:XYf:X\to Y, we have Cf=ΣFfC f = \Sigma F f, and so a map ACfA \to C f is the same as a map AΣFfA \to \Sigma F f, and hence to a map ΩAFf\Omega A \to F f. Now the definition of FfF f as a homotopy fiber says this is the same as a commutative square

ΩAXf0Y\begin{CD} \Omega A @>>> X\\ @VVV @VVfV \\ 0 @>>> Y \end{CD}

which is a map 0ΩAf0_*\Omega A \to f.

view this post on Zulip Tobias Fritz (May 11 2021 at 16:46):

Thanks, that's really beautiful!

view this post on Zulip Tobias Fritz (May 11 2021 at 16:54):

So would it make sense to try and consider two (,1)(\infty,1)-categories together with an infinite string of adjoints between them as a formal context for stability? Perhaps with the additional requirement of the "central" three functors should form an (\infty-version of) an adjoint cylinder, or some other idempotency requirement along these lines? How much of homological algebra could one expect to get like this? Would every object in the "formal" category of arrows give rise to a long exact sequence (generalizing the usual one for mapping cones)?

view this post on Zulip Peter Arndt (May 11 2021 at 17:11):

Haha, part of this thread has been an almost perfect copy of this one.