You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
I was reading the start of Leinster's "Galois Theory" (here). On page 15, this example of a group action is provided:
Let be the 48-element group of isometries (rotations and reflections) of a cube. Then acts on the 6-element set of faces of the cube: any isometry maps faces to faces.
Intuitively, specifying a way to transform a cube so that it "lands back on itself" provides an induced permutation of the faces of the cube.
This leads me wonder: When (and how) can we induce automorphisms of one object from automorphisms of a different object?
I find it helpful to think about this in the category of sets. Consider the set together with the subset . Then there are lots of automorphisms of that don't induce automorphisms of in a nice way. For example, the permutation does not nicely induce a permutation of , because under this permutation gets mapped to an element outside of .
Motivated by this, I started considering commutative squares like this one:
commutative square
Here, and are objects in some category , is an automorphism, and is a monomorphism. The intuitive intent is that the square commuting ensures that the -part of gets mapped to itself under . We can ask under what conditions a will exist so that the square commutes. When does exist and is an automorphism, we might say it is the automorphism of induced by the automorphism . By the way, I believe that if exists, it is unique, because if , then , because is a monomorphism.
In this context, we can consider a few questions:
Although I mention some specific questions above for concreteness, it could be interesting to discuss related concepts in this direction too! So please don't hesitate to mention something just because it doesn't directly answer one of my specific questions.
I think for finite sets in classical foundations, will always be an automorphism if it exists; for infinite sets you probably need something else -- probably for the square to be a pullback.
As a concrete counterexample, let , , and with the inclusion. Then exists, but is not an automorphism of .
If pulls back to itself along an isomorphism, then the other projection of the pullback is an isomorphism: take the unique arrow from Y to Y induced by the arrows and , it will be a section of because induced it and a retraction of because and so has the same cone as (and is therefore identical to) .
Similarly if a square like this exists with , automorphisms, it is a pullback because given a pullback cone where , induces the cone ( is immediate, because ). So being a pullback is exactly enough.
(Oh, and the inducing morphism is unique because is a mono. Or because is an iso hence a mono. Take your pick.)
Mike Shulman said:
As a concrete counterexample, let , , and with the inclusion. Then exists, but is not an automorphism of .
Ah, so sometimes is not an automorphism. I guess that means my plan for inducing automorphisms doesn't always work out!
(In this case I think also adds one to each , but this is not a bijection and hence not an automorphism of in .)
If what you're after is some way of inducing automorphisms on a subobject, then you may want to consider the stabilizer subgroup of that subobject. In set-theoretic language, if a group acts on a set , and is a subset of , for we define , and then the stabilizer of is . Your hypothesis of the existence of corresponds in this language to asking that , which isn't strong enough to yield a subgroup of , but the stronger condition is.
In categorical language, corresponds to asking that the composite is equal to "as a subobject of ", which means that they are isomorphic (necessarily uniquely) in the slice category over . This amounts to explicitly requiring the existence of a that is an isomorphism, so from this point of view we're just solving the problem by fiat. However, the notion of stabilizer of a subobject is a fairly well-studied one, so at least it makes a connection to well-known concepts.
And thanks @James Deikun for thinking about this! However, I'm still learning the basics of category theory, and it will take me some work to understand your response. If I understand correctly, you are considering the case where together with maps and is a pullback of the diagram corresponding to the maps and .
Considering the case where the diagram is a pullback wouldn't have occurred to me. I guess I don't have a lot of intuition for when pullbacks are relevant yet, or what they are really like!
I don't understand what this means: "take the unique arrow from Y to Y induced by the arrows and ". We have that is a morphism from to , and of course goes from to . So I'm assuming there is some standard way of inducing a morphism from to given a morphism from to and a morphism from to , using a pullback diagram of the form pictured above. However, I don't know what this way is!
EDIT:
Ah, I think I see the idea! The maps and together with would provide another cone over the diagram corresponding to the maps and . Then we want to use the universal property of the pullback to induce .
I'll try and see how much further I can get, understanding this.
Mike Shulman said:
Your hypothesis of the existence of corresponds in this language to asking that , which isn't strong enough to yield a subgroup of , but the stronger condition is.
I think this was illustrated in that example above, where the action of the automorphism of (where and for each ) on is such that , but .
James Deikun said:
If pulls back to itself along an isomorphism, then the other projection of the pullback is an isomorphism: take the unique arrow from Y to Y induced by the arrows and , it will be a section of because induced it and a retraction of because and so has the same cone as (and is therefore identical to) .
I think I now follow all of this! The idea that a morphism like can have a cone confused me for a while. I think the idea is that we can get a new cone from the pullback cone by precomposing at the apex using . That's pretty cool - I don't think I'd really realized you can get new cones from old ones in this way.
The technique of finding two cone morphisms to the pullback cone, each having the same source cone, and then concluding these two cone morphisms are the same (because there is a unique cone morphism to the pullback cone from any other cone over the appropriate diagram) was also very interesting to see.
(By the way, I think it should be , not in the last sentence).
Ah, yes, you're right. Fixed.
As for "why a pullback in the first place", a pullback of two monos in displays the intersection of two subsets, so generalizing from that it seemed likely to work.
James Deikun said:
Similarly if a square like this exists with , automorphisms, it is a pullback because given a pullback cone where , induces the cone ( is immediate, because ). So being a pullback is exactly enough.
And this all makes sense to me as well! Hooray!
So, in summary, the original commutative square is a pullback square if and only if is an automorphism.
James Deikun said:
As for "why a pullback in the first place", a pullback of two monos in displays the intersection of two subsets, so generalizing from that it seemed likely to work.
Thanks for explaining! This helps provide some additional intuition (for me) regarding what a pullback is like.