You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Let be a functor. Let be an equivalence relationship on the objects of . We say that preserves when .
Two questions:
Notice this is actually a question about maps of sets (for large enough notions of sets)!
For (1), what do you mean discover?
There might be some hope to characterize those ~ preserved by but enumerating them is a whole other can of worms
Some easy equivalence relations preserved by all functors:
Matteo Capucci (he/him) said:
Notice this is actually a question about maps of sets (for large enough notions of sets)!
Could you elaborate on what you mean by the above statement?
Matteo Capucci (he/him) said:
For (1), what do you mean discover?
Both characterization and enumeration sound interesting to me.
For context, I would like to think about what kinds of "properties" are preserved by an imaging process. Ideally this would help in the following context: I have an imaging process, and I want to figure out what I can detect about objects with it.
I think this is another equivalence relationship preserved by a functor :
Let exactly when .
This equivalence relationship is intuitively "sent to same observation by ".
Here's another one, assuming I didn't mix up something:
Let .
First we show this is an equivalence relationship.
for any .
If , then , with any objects in .
If and for any objects in , then we have and and so , which implies .
Now we show the equivalence relationship is preserved by .
Let . Then we have , which implies , because functors send isomorphic objects to isomorphic objects. But implies that , by definition of our equivalence relationship. So, .
This last equivalence relationship is intuitively "sent to isomorphic observations by ".
You can do the same for the other two examples that Joshua gave: since "homomorphically equivalent" and "connected" are preserved by any functor, or are further equivalence relations preserved by .
You might find this paper interesting: http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/volumes/1999/n11/n11.pdf
Morgan Rogers (he/him) said:
You can do the same for the other two examples that Joshua gave: since "homomorphically equivalent" and "connected" are preserved by any functor, or are further equivalence relations preserved by .
I suppose this procedure always works? Say is an equivalence relationship preserved by . Then let be the equivalence relationship defined by . We want to show is preserved by .
Let's check that really is an equivalence relationship.
Let's check that is preserved by .
, where we use the fact that is preserved by .
Then as desired.
Sam Speight said:
You might find this paper interesting: http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/volumes/1999/n11/n11.pdf
That is interesting, thanks for sharing it!
Can we get more equivalence relationships using the strategy above?
Let be an equivalence relationship on preserved by .
We saw above that the equivalence relationship defined by is also an equivalence relationship preserved by .
Let us call the equivalence relationship generated from in this way by the name .
If is an equivalence relationship preserved by , then so is .
This means that is also an equivalence relationship preserved by .
In general should be an equivalence relationship preserved by , for any positive integer .
Let's see what is for .
.
It appears that "isomorphic after two applications of " is another equivalence relationship on preserved by . More generally, "eventually isomorphic after enough applications of " should be another equivalence relationship preserved by .
You've implicitly discovered that if one has any collection of equivalence relations preserved by then their intersection is also preserved by . That lends some structure to your search ;)
Another equivalence relation: the transitive closure of the relation such that either or is identity.
In general, if is a relation preserved by , its transitive closure is an equivalence relation preserved by
Another example: for all