You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
(Previously "differential 2-rigs", but there's been a little of a fight about the correct name :grinning: )
So, the idea is really simple, and I will lazily summarise it in the abstract of the draft-of-a-paper I am writing. (Jokes apart, I find it quite self-explanatory of the general motivation I had, when this project began)
Now, if is a rig category, in the sense that a monoidal structure distributes over coproducts, a derivation is just an endofunctor with the property that
.
As a general rule, one knows to be after some deep Mathematics when a seemingly innocuous assumption yields unexpected or counterintuitive results . This is the case here, because from these very natural assumptions most of the theory of differential rings carries over, with one, eminent, painful exception: there is absolutely no reason why the derivative of the monoidal unit is zero (=the initial object of the rig).
Let me offend your intelligence by recalling that if if is a differential ring, with derivation , then ; now, since the additive monoid of is cancellative, we get . In fact, in differential semiring theory, the most you can get is that the derivative of is an additive idempotent. Now, some authors require as an axiom of a differential semiring, essentially because if this is not required, is not well-defined: , which in its own right is , which... on the other hand, there are examples of semirings where every object is an additive idempotent (posets with , an eminent instance of which are co-Heyting algebras, that carry interesting operations that satisfy the axioms of a derivation.
When one moves to true categories things get way hairier, essentially because entails a whole lot of counterintuitive properties: I will list the ones that I found until now, in discussions with @Nathanael Arkor @Fabrizio Genovese (with which this ended up being a joint work) @Daniele Palombi and others (I get pretty pushy when there's mathematics I like and I can't get it right :grinning: )
First, must be "empty or big", in the sense that -for example in the category of sets- a set such that is either empty or infinite.
On the other hand, in the category of _finite_ sets, can only be empty; same in the category of finite dimensional vector spaces, where has 0 (thus the zero space) as unique solution. Same, in every category with a decent choice of dimension . (What are examples of these categories? Do they have a name)?
On another hand, sometimes is forced to have just trivial solutions due to the request that this equality is in some sense natural; for example, let be a derivation in a category of functors ; then, is a functor such that , and naturally so; such functors are few, because no bijection can be natural if the domain is just a little bit nontrivial. I have asked this question for the exact purpose of establishing this obstruction result.
In an abstract category of course you can't uniquely attach to an object information about how big it is; but you still have morphisms and the Yoneda lemma! So, let's stick in the hom-set for a generic object ; the fact that yields . Now _this_ is interesting, because can only be empty, a singleton or infinite. Let me sum up: a property of that -at least a priori- has nothing to do with its size, the presence of a differential structure, imposes some conditions on the numerosity of some of its hom-sets; if a category is finite, thus, is either empty or a singleton, and in particular it must be a singleton when . Again, having a differential structure and being finite entails that is a "rigid" object, in the sense that the monoid of endomorphisms of is trivial.
More on this: whenever there is an extension in , there must be a monomorphism , so that if the domain, endomorphisms of , is infinite, the codomain, arrows , can only be bigger. The endomorphisms of clearly are "something special"! And this is why I would like to get to know them better: let for short; then, from one easily gets, by induction, that for every finite . How many monoids with this property do you know, apart the terminal one?
Let's go deeper in the white rabbit's hole: if , this means that is naturally a coalgebra for the "leave it or double it" functor , in such a way that there is a unique map
between and the terminal coalgebra of ; but wait, in the category of topological space is the Cantor set! What just happened here? Is the map an epi, a mono in general?
So. All these questions are vague and somewhat alluding to the fact that I do not have a clear picture of what's going on: indeed, I have no idea which wa to turn: what am I after? "What is" the derivative of 1 in a differential ring, like, really? How shall one interpret each of the strange properties that I have outlined?
Another interesting idea related to the perks and shortcomings of being is the following: as an endofunctor, might have interesting fixed points, and there is a standard procedure to build its initial algebra and terminal coalgebra. One could legitimately call such an object "Eulerian" or "Neperian", for obvious reasons (the most reasonable is that "exponential object" already means something else).
Initial algebras are trivial, in that by using the Leibniz rule. On the other hand, the triviality of terminal coalgebras is governed by , in the sense that (assuming the terminal object is the monoidal unit, that's what is called a semicartesian monoidal category)
and the first ordinal for which the transition morphism is invertible realises the terminal coalgebra. Now, what is this map? What is the result of applying many times to ? Well, since , and is linear, , thus the entire cochain is made by coalgebras for the functor (even more, by coalgebras whose coalgebra map is invertible: how many such algebras are there? What's their shape?).
Yeah, I feel like sometimes gives us a very coarse way of representing cardinality within . In Set theory, we "measure:" size of sets by using injections. This is due to Hartog's lemma, which basicaly says that for any two sets you have either an injection or the other way around. Bernstein's theorem instead says that if you have monos both ways, then are in bijection. This is what allows us to order sets using cardinality.
In here, if is big, meaning that is infinite, then a monomorphism guarantees that there is a mono . Hence, the generalized elements of of type are infinite, and is in some sense "big". I feel there is much more to say about this if one looks deep enough...
Very nice! Can you tell a bit more about the context: why are you interested in differential rig categories? What motivated this definition?
To my knowledge, literally nothing.
I mean, I don't see any immediate motivating application. I think it started as a cool set of mathematically pertinent questions that Fosco had
And you know, you ask questions, give more answers, connect the points, keep asking more questions, ...
This is also why we do not have a precise direction for this at the moment. This work can evolve in many multiple ways and we literally have no real bias. For me, it's just a matter of understanding how much more gas there's in the tank, and where can we get from here :smile:
Antonin Delpeuch said:
Very nice! Can you tell a bit more about the context: why are you interested in differential rig categories? What motivated this definition?
I just find it a very natural notion and the many examples prove it is.
But I might be misunderstanding the question: are you asking if a particular example motivated the definition? Yes (combinatorial species) and no (I started to think about them after having drafted the first definition of a derivation on a category). Same with "Brzozowski derivatives", whose existence I didn't even suspected before :smile:
Ah ok, I did not know about combinatorial species, that totally explains the motivation :)
Should cancellation also happen in a rig? :thinking:
It seems reasonable to require
even for a rig, where
Eric Forgy said:
Should cancellation also happen in a rig? :thinking:
It seems reasonable to require
even for a rig, where
[Ah, you just said what was 2, sorry] :grinning:
Same as Todd's comment below, yes.
Boolean algebras are rigs. But doesn't imply .
Eric Forgy said:
Should cancellation also happen in a rig? :thinking:
Not necessarily. A rig is a monoid object in . To tweak that definition to require extra properties just because they hold in rings and you like them would be like drawing a picture of a deer in the background of the Mona Lisa just because you like pictures with deer in them. Or worse, actually.
Is "endofunctor with the property that [isomorphisms]" shorthand for endofunctor equipped with isomorphisms satisfying some unstated coherence laws?
Reid Barton said:
Is "endofunctor with the property that [isomorphisms]" shorthand for endofunctor equipped with isomorphisms satisfying some unstated coherence laws?
To await a coherence law, is itself a coherence law.
Is that some kinda Zen thing?
It'a also a very popular meme in Italy, coming from a dumb TV ad where they said "To await for pleasure is itself pleasure", or something like that :grinning:
Oh.
Well, Campari took the tagline from a minor German philosopher, so I would say it is the exact opposite of a Zen thing.
Even more so because another quote from this guy's work is
It is the mark of great people to treat trifles as trifles and important matters as important.
(Hamburgische Dramaturgie (1767 - 1769), Vierunddreißigstes Stück Den 25. August 1767)
whereas Laozi LXIII says
大小多少,
報怨以德。
圖難于其易,
為大于其細。
天下難事必作于易,
天下大事必作于細,
是以聖人終不為大,
故能成其大。
-
Enlarge the belittled, increase the lessened,
Reward condemnation with Virtue.
Complexity is drawn from simplicity,
Greatness is found in triviality.
Problematic complexities must be resolved in simplicity,
Great accomplishments must be built on trivialities,
Hence the master continues to be unconcerned with great deeds,
Therefore is capable of accomplishing greatness.
Someone has a better name than "Leibnizator" for the cell here?
also, do these coherence conditions remind you of something else?
"Leibnizator" sounds like the right name for the cell version of the Leibniz law, it's not significantly weirder than "pentagonator"
Although, on the basis that to an English speaker, German names make good supervillain names, it makes me think of this.....
"And now, watch as I pull this lever on the Leibnizator, behold as it begins producing my army of Leibniz clones! And you, Goody Man, cannot stop me! Muahahahahaha!" / "Dr. Leibniz, you fiend! You won't get away with this!"
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Usrk5HR1U4I
+1 for Leibnizator
Update: next Tuesday I will give an informal talk to my colleagues here in taltech about this whole story.
Feel free to join! Here the coordinates of the event; the title of the event contains a direct link to the zoom room.
Hope I'll meet you there!
So, I am slowly making progress, and I have a new question.
Let's state it for rings for the moment; say is a differential ring and a linear topology that makes sense of infinite products like
now, is there a way to prove the "infinite Leibniz rule" algebraically, without resorting to any analtyic technique? The rule is
and ideally, the proof would go as follows:
and now "one sees" that the claim holds. Now
To make the argument more formal, you could say the infinite products and coproducts are "limits" of finite ones (in some sense of "limit", to be determined), and assume that the derivation can be passed through these "limits", and thus reduce the infinite Leibniz rule to the finite one.
Thanks, @John Baez !
The proof I know is for sequences of holomorphic functions: if is such a sequence, then
the proof, however, takes the logarithm of the product and uses the logarithmic derivative rule:
I was wondering if there's a proof for differential-topological rings that one can try to adapt: afaicu the fact that a differential on a ring lifts to a continuous operator really depends on many petty details.
A lot of analysis is the study of "petty details" like this.
John Baez said:
A lot of analysis is the study of "petty details" like this.
"I have always disliked analysis."
P.J. Freyd
Where's that from, Fosco?
(Normally, mathematicians declaring they dislike a certain field doesn't improve my opinion of them.)
His paper 'Algebraic Real Analysis' if I recall correctly.
http://www.tac.mta.ca/tac/volumes/20/10/20-10abs.html
It's worth reading the appendix which is where that quote appears. I don't think it is meant to be derogatory. And anyway, the appendix ends with "... but, at least, now I like analysis."
Good: if you don't like something about a field, the noble path is to fix it.
Well, that's good! And more what I would expect from Freyd: a creative response rather than just "I don't like it". Thanks for adding that.
Todd Trimble said:
Well, that's good! And more what I would expect from Freyd: a creative response rather than just "I don't like it". Thanks for adding that.
Why you don't like Freyd? :grinning:
Are you preparing a paper that starts with "I have always disliked P.J. Freyd" and ends with "...but at least, now, I lke Peter Freyd"?
What?
I was just kidding: I know Freyd solely from his work, and I consider him one of the most brilliant category theorists ever; instead you seem of a different advice: why?
I think you may have misread Todd's message :)
Nope, I agree with you. I asked where he said that, so I could get a better idea of the context.
haha! Yes, thanks Nathanael: I misread: I thought you said "more than what I would expect from Freyd"
so, my bad! Hope the misunderstanding is solved :smile:
No problem -- yes, it's resolved.
I have just one last question left here, and then I can turn my attention into something else ;-) or different.
As we all know, if is a differential ring and a derivation, there is a nice formula for the derivative of a multiplicative unit :
(if the ring is not commutative, ). Interesting fact is that if is a multiplicative unit in a _semi_ ring, the fact that it also has an additive inveres comes for free using the Leibniz rule provided )
What about categories now?!
Let's study the first condition and see where it goes: let's say (monoidal) has a right dual , this means that regarding as a bicategory, has a right adjoint: this in turn means that
(I the monoidal unit) satisfy the triangle identities. Let's concentrate on one of them:
and let's see f there any chance to find an expression for in terms of .
In particular let's derive the triangle identity: if I'm not wrong one gets
from this one gets diagrams
and I'm interested in the red arrows, that can be composed in a map . In a proper sense (I am willingly hiding some coherence under the carpet), the object- and morphism-wise sum of these maps is just the derivative of the composition of unitors
This means that the square
commutes, if the vertical maps are leibnization isomorphisms, and the red upper row is the sum we were trying to compute.
What now? What do you think?