You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Yesterday James Dolan asked me this puzzle, and then told me the answer:
For any bicategory there's a bicategory with the same objects as , where the morphisms are adjunctions in , and the 2-morphisms are some well-known maps between adjunctions.
For example if , is the usual 2-category where morphisms are adjoint functors.
Puzzle. What are morphisms in ?
You have four functors, two adjunctions. The internal-internal unit and counit actually pan out to give an internal unit and counit giving an adjunction between the left of the left and the left of the right, which of course forces the left of the right to be the same as the right of the left. So an adjoint triple.
Furthermore iterating this argument shows that the morphisms in are adjoint -strings!
It's also worth noting that you can go one step below the level of functors. Functors are themselves adjunctions of profunctors. So adjoint -tuples of functors are adjoint -tuples of profunctors.
Hmmm... I wonder if there's a universal way to go down a level. Does have an adjoint?
I don't know if has an adjoint, but it reminds me of something else: there's an adjunction between adjunctions and monads.
and
and the second construction can be seen as a right adjoint of the first, if I've got my head on straight. (I think the Kleisli construction is the left adjoint. But maybe it's the other way round!)
There should be some very general way to say this, but you need some conditions to build an "Eilenberg-Moore object" for a monad in a bicategory, I think. I guess a bunch of this was handled in Lack and Street's papers on the formal theory of monads, but I've never carefully read those.
plays an important role in the specification of modal type theories for adjoint strings, particularly cohesion. When you specify a 2-category as the "mode theory" for a type theory, then every morphism in gives rise to an adjoint pair of modal operators, a "positive" one (with a left universal property) and a "negative" one (with a right universal property). Thus, if you want an adjoint triple of modal operators, you can achieve that by specifying an adjoint pair of morphisms in .
A more category-theoretic way of saying something similar is that if is a bifibration (i.e. both a fibration and an opfibration), then every morphism in gives rise to an adjoint pair of functors between the fibers over its domain and codomain. Therefore, an adjoint pair of morphisms in gives rise to an adjoint triple of functors between these fibers.
Oscar Cunningham said:
It's also worth noting that you can go one step below the level of functors. Functors are themselves adjunctions of profunctors. So adjoint -tuples of functors are adjoint -tuples of profunctors.
Hmmm... I wonder if there's a universal way to go down a level. Does have an adjoint?
For a (complete enough) -category , one can construct its -category of two-sided discrete fibrations . Given a -cell , I think you get an adjoint pair in by considering the adequate comma objects.
In the other direction, an adjunction of two-sided discrete fibrations (), induce representably a family of adjunctions between profunctors and naturally in , which then correspond to a family of functors naturally in , hence to a -cell from to in .
This let me think that might be equivalent to whenever the construction makes sense, providing some kind of inverse construction to .
Interesting. So basically take the definition of profunctors in terms of functors and repeat it in an arbitrary -category. I can't quite see what this gives when you apply it to , but it's not just because there's a functor from to but if there was an object with an adjunction to both and then we could compose a functor going the other way.
A similar argument also shows that cannot be the underlying functor of a monad or a comonad.
If is the walking adjunction (the -category with two objects and a single adjunction between these), then the walking arrow -category and the discrete -category with two objects. There is no functor from to and no functor from to , so the former shows that cannot be equipped with a comultiplication, and the latter that it cannot be equipped with a unit.
There are functors between those categories but they're all constant. Is that enough?
Right, I have been too hasty. But in both cases you have to satisfy unitality/counitality equations that prevent constant functors to be valid solutions.