You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
I would like to prove that if is a functor with left and adjoint and:
$\begin{enumerate}
\item reflects isomorphisms
\item has coequalizers of reflexive pairs
\item preserves coequalizers of reflexive pairs
\end{enumerate}$
then the adjunction is a monadic adjunction.
Under these assumptions, I can prove that the canonical comparison functor is essentially surjective. Given an algebra , the parallel pair is reflexive because is a section of both. It follows that there is a coequalizer for the pair .
is coequalizer of , but so is , hence there exists an isomorphism such that $Uh = \gamma; \theta$. To prove that is an algebra morphism it suffices to check that .
This shows that the comparison functor is essentially surjective. It remains to show that it is fully faithful.
Is there a way to use latex here?
Surround with two $ signs instead of one. Or use a ```math block.
(I moved this to another topic.) I think the statement you're trying to prove is called the crude monadicity theorem. It's an immediate consquence of the precise monadicity theorem that gives necessary and sufficient conditions for a functor to be monadic, since its hypotheses are strictly stronger, so any reference that proves the precise monadicity theorem should show how to complete your proof as well. Is there a particular point you're stuck on?
Mike Shulman said:
(I moved this to another topic.) I think the statement you're trying to prove is called the crude monadicity theorem. It's an immediate consquence of the precise monadicity theorem that gives necessary and sufficient conditions for a functor to be monadic, since its hypotheses are strictly stronger, so any reference that proves the precise monadicity theorem should show how to complete your proof as well. Is there a particular point you're stuck on?
By "precise monadicity theorem" do you mean the theorem "An adjunction is monadic if and only if creates coequalizers of -split pairs"?
Is the crude monadicity theorem a consequence of this theorem?
In the text have written above, I am half-way of proving the crude monadicity theorem, it only remains to prove that the comparison functor is fully faithfull, which unfortunately I do not know how to do right now.
I'm not sure if it's possible to deduce the crude monadicity theorem (CTT) directly from the precise one (PTT) stated in that way. But the U-split coequalizers that are used in the proof of PTT are, in fact, also reflexive; so the same proof of the "if" direction of PTT is a proof of CTT. Some references, like Toposes, triples, and theories, include reflexivity in the statement of PTT.
Thank you for recommending the texts Toposes, triples, and theories. I am reading it now
Lucas Queiroz said:
I would like to prove that if is a functor with left and adjoint and:
$\begin{enumerate}
\item reflects isomorphisms
\item has coequalizers of reflexive pairs
\item preserves coequalizers of reflexive pairs
\end{enumerate}$then the adjunction is a monadic adjunction.
Under these assumptions, I can prove that the canonical comparison functor is essentially surjective. Given an algebra , the parallel pair is reflexive because is a section of both. It follows that there is a coequalizer for the pair .
is coequalizer of , but so is , hence there exists an isomorphism such that $Uh = \gamma; \theta$. To prove that is an algebra morphism it suffices to check that .
This shows that the comparison functor is essentially surjective. It remains to show that it is fully faithful.
@Mike Shulman I am still having some difficult in proving that is fully faithful. Can you give some hints please?
I'm sorry, I don't have the time to walk you through it more explicitly. Maybe someone else here will, or you can check some other references if TTT is too hard to follow.
See Mac Lane-Moerdijk, Sheaves in Geometry and Logic, for a direct proof.
@Todd Trimble: I see, indeed Sheaves in Geometry and Logic proves the result I want on page 179. I will try to read this proof