You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
In the nLab, A functor is said to preserve a limit of a diagram if is a limit of . Howerver, I've seen other sources that define preservation of limits as an isomorphim , especially in the context of continuous functors. The 1st definition obviously induces the isomorphism, but I can't seem to figure out exactly when the isomorphism implies the 1st definition. Does anyone have any pointers?
Sources:
https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/preserved+limit
https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/continuous+functor
EDIT:
After playing around with this a bit, I realized that the isomorphism had to be an isomorphism of _cones_, not an isomorphism between apexes!
Precisely, a limit is not just an object, but it is defined as a (universal) cone.
So a functor preserves a limit of a diagram (where is an object of and is the edges of a cone) if and only if is a limit of .
This is equivalent to (the existence of a limit of in and) the existence of an isomorphism of cones because, in general, a cone is a limit cone if and only if it is isomorphic to some limit cone.
In response to the original question, which may have turned out not to be what you meant to ask: the paper Limit Preservation from Naturality by Caccamo–Winskel describes sufficient conditions for such an isomorphism to imply limit-preservation.
I think this maybe obscures the main point though; if and have limits, then for any functor , there's always a canonical map (exercise); preserves the limit of if and only if this map is an isomorphism.
It's somewhat tiresome to write out any of the exact definitions of "preserves limits", especially if lacking the vocabulary of limit cones, and so it's common to see abuses like "" to mean that the canonical map is an isomorphism or " is a limit of " to mean via the maps induced by and the cone morphisms for the original limit and .
Right, I think this convention that is often a canonical isomorphism, rather than an arbitrary one, can be easy to not notice when learning, especially as this is sometimes completely implicit. (The abstract from the paper above makes this clear, though.)
It's fun to try to dream up examples where , the mere existence of some isomorphism, holds but is not good enough.
on the flip side, Steve Lack has a paper in which he shows that -- contrary to what you'd expect -- in certain special cases some isomorphism is actually good enough https://arxiv.org/pdf/0912.2126.pdf.