You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
The category of affine schemes over , denoted , is the opposite of the category of commutative algebras over the field . We say an affine scheme is exponentiable if the functor
has a right adjoint. In other words, maps are in natural bijection to maps .
The most famous example of an exponentiable affine scheme is the walking tangent vector , whose corresponding commutative algebra is . Lawvere pointed out that this means the tangent bundle of any affine scheme is simply : you can think of a tangent vector in either as a map or as a map .
So, what are all the exponentiable affine schemes?
@Todd Trimble reported a wonderful fact, namely that an affine scheme is exponentiable iff its corresponding commutative algebra is finite-dimensional!
He says this was proved by Susan Niefield.
Where's the reference to this - and even better, how do you prove it? Is it hard to prove?
I forget where, but no, I don't think it's hard to prove. The corresponding fact about the coordinate algebra is that preserves limits. I'll think about the proof if no one else comes along (and I hope I remembered correctly!).
See Theorem 4.3 here.
What happens when k is generalised from being a field? Say to a local ring, a Dedekind domain, or all the way to a ring?
I should have said, but see Theorem 4.3. ;-) Just kidding. For a commutative ring, the underlying module of the coordinate algebra needs to be finitely generated and projective: that's necessary and sufficient.
Let me give it a try. An endofunctor on a locally presentable category has a left adjoint iff it preserves colimits, and is locally presentable. So is "co-locally presentable", and for some affine scheme we have
has a right adjoint iff it preserves limits.
I might as well do the case where is any commutative ring.
So we just need to show preserves limits iff the corresponding commutative algebra has an underlying -module that's finitely generated and projective.
But let's work purely with commutative algebras and let .
The product in is the coproduct in which is none other than , "tensoring over ".
So we just need to show preserves limits iff the underlying -module of is finitely generated projective.
This sounds almost like some standard facts about -modules, but we have to be a little careful since our condition here is that preserves limits in , not in .
Hmm, but the forgetful functor is a right adjoint, so it preserves limits. And this functor is also monadic, right? - so it also reflects limits - right?
If I'm not screwing up, this means preserves limits in iff it preserves limits in . Is this correct? I'm not very good at this stuff....
Anyway, if I haven't screwed up it's enough to show preserves limits iff is a finitely generated projective module.
Oh shoot, yes. I should have said preserves limits earlier. My bad. I'll go back and edit in a bit.
Anyway, if is f.g. projective, then so is the linear dual (and in fact they're dual to each other). But if is f.g. projective, what that really means is that preserves colimits (projective gives you preservation of finite colimits, and finitely generated gives you preservation of filtered colimits, and the two together give you preservation of all colimits).
Okay, so what? Well, a functor that preserves colimits must be of the form for some , and that is . So for f.g. projective, we get . The right side is more simply . But for , that is even more simply still, .
So we've managed to show that for f.g. projective, that . But now lookie here: the right side, being a covariant hom-functor, preserves limits!! Which is what you wanted to show for .
It's kind of a sneaky twisted little argument. Ultimately it may be easier to think about all this from the standpoint of monoidal duals, but anyway it's a pleasant argument.
Wow, this is all very nice. To really get the desired "iff" - an affine scheme is exponentiable iff the corresponding commutative algebra is f.g. projective - we need the converse of the work you did. I think a key bit here is that the internal hom
preserves colimits iff is f.g. projective.
Yes indeed. All this is part and parcel of Morita theory, where objects of the Cauchy completion are tantamount to adjoint pairs of bimodules, harking back to Lawvere's metric spaces where he first introduced categorical Cauchy completion: he defined this in terms of adjoint bimodules. (You and I and maybe Joe was there too -- we were talking about this once.)
The nLab reminds me that the external hom
preserved filtered colimits iff is finitely generated, and this is really a general fact about varieties in universal algebra, nothing special about modules of rings.
Insofar as the Cauchy completion of a ring is its category of f.g. projective modules, you see how this fits together.
Umm, no I don't.
Yeah, I think there the result should be about finitely presentable algebras, if you're speaking about varieties generally.
Sorry. Let me slow down. (I often feel hurried up in these Zulip discussions, unfortunately. Whereas in real life, I'm a slow-talking Southern boy.)
I was busy thinking about the more humdrum issue of the last step: why
preserved finite colimits iff projective. I guess this is also easy.
Todd Trimble said:
Sorry. Let me slow down. (I often feel hurried up in these Zulip discussions, unfortunately. Whereas in real life, I'm a slow-talking Southern boy.)
Yeah, I like it when in "real life" (meaning Zoom) you patiently demonstrate something step by step on the whiteboard.
Yes. Finite biproducts (so finite coproducts) are automatic. The projective part is about preserving coequalizers.
I don't know. Should we say more about that?
I'll take that as a "sure".
Sure! I was trying to formulate a confusion I'm having....
.... but I was confused about what the confusion was.
It's about "homming out of projectives preserves epis" versus "homming out projectives preserves coequalizers".
I guess we're in a situation (namely a module category) where every epi is a regular epi, so we can use that to show the "homming out of B preserves epis" iff "homming out of B preserves coequalizers".
Right. Well, I think it's a bit tricky when you put it in that generality, so I personally would do this: first show that for any module , that preserves short exact sequences .
(I don't think that preserving regular epis is the same as preserving coequalizers, even if you're in a regular category!)
(Okay, thanks.)
So then, the only missing piece would be to show preservation of exactness at in a short exact sequence
.
That's where you need only preservation of epis.
So this mode of argumentation is pretty tied to abelian categories.
Maybe someone listening in can explain it better! But this is what I have at the moment.
Okay, I think I know this classic sort of stuff; i.e. having played with homological algebra enough I know I can prove the facts you're mentioning, at least if I think a bit. I was just starting to wonder how much of this motto
"homming out of B preserves filtered colimits iff B is finitely generated and finite colimits iff B is projective."
generalizes to an arbitrary variety. This is part of trying to upgrade my understanding of how homological algebra fits into more general ideas.
The first part of the motto works in any variety. But not the second?
For the first part of the motto, replace "finitely generated" by "finitely presentable".
Whoops!
So modules of rings are special in that finitely generated modules are automatically finitely presentable?
Yes, that's true.
Oh wait. Is that true? I'm suddenly worried about Noetherian....
Ugh, I'm confused enough that I decided to delete my comment just now.
I now believe that finitely generated R-modules are not necessarily finitely presented, but finitely generated projective ones are. So maybe this is why people run around acting like "finitely generated" and "projective" are the key ideas when playing with modules, when more generally, for other varieties, maybe we should be saying "finitely presented" and... something.
Okay, the whole point is that f.g. projective means having a retract of a f.g. free module -- and those last behave very well.
I'm looking for a slogan, valid for varieties, of the form
"homming out of B preserves filtered colimits iff B is finitely presented and finite colimits iff B is ????."
So then homming out of an object preserves all colimits iff it's finitely presented and ????.
Yeah, hm. Not thinking especially clearly at the moment...
Anyway, you have satisfied my original desire to understand exponentiable affine schemes. You've done it so elegantly that I'm itching to generalize this result to categories that are opposites of varieties... but it's not really important.
You deserve an answer to that question though.
(And feel I should know this. I think I need to step away from the computer for a moment!)
If tensoring with something preserves finite limits it's called "flat"... if Homming out of something preserves finite colimits it is called "????".
The nlab calls [[tiny+object]] one that preserves all small colimits, and does not seem to have anything in-between these and a [[small+object]] (preserving directed colimits). They do, however, mention that Kelly called them small-projective, so maybe finite-projective would be an appropriate name.
John Baez said:
I was busy thinking about the more humdrum issue of the last step: why
preserved finite colimits iff projective. I guess this is also easy.
Speaking of this nlab page, they example they give for categories of modules (or any with a zero object) seems to show that this will not be true if you consider as a -enriched category, that is if you put as the codomain of the corepresentable functor, so you do need to do as Todd Trimble above and work "abelianly".
Yes. The only thing I'll say at the moment is that if the ambient category is a variety of algebras, then this preserving colimits is quite rare, since typically coproducts in that category behave tend to behave very differently from coproducts of sets. This might help explain why we're not coughing up names that readily in this generality.
Oh, you were making the same point. (And I was a principal author of that nLab article!)
I haven't read all the above discussion, but this was indeed proved by Niefield. I didn't find it completely trivial to use her argument to construct the exponential explicitly, so I gave an explicit description in terms of generators and relations in Theorem 4.2.1 of by PhD thesis. (Technically I do it for commutative quantales, but change the joins to sums and the situation for commutative rings is identical.)
Yeah, I think that following on David’s and Todd’s recent points, there is no completion of the slogan for when maps out of an object in an arbitrary variety commute with finite colimits because that simply never happens. The misleading thing about module categories is that they’re presheaf categories in the enriched sense, and it’s reasonable to hope for objects maps out of which commute with all colimits in presheaf categories, but basically never otherwise. Just consider when maps out of even a free algebra on one generator commute with coproducts: only if coproducts are disjoint, which is highly uncharacteristic of algebraic categories. In fact I wouldn’t be shocked if this property will only happen in a variety that can be presented via a theory with only unary operations, ie one of presheaf type.
Regular projective objects, maps out of which commute with regular epis, are certainly very important in algebraic categories since specifically monadic categories are characterized as being exact with a regular projective generator. These things are retracts of frees and so maps out will commute with whatever colimits maps out of frees commute with, which seems like all one can reasonably ask for to me.
I think we also can’t usually ask for maps out of the regular projectives to commute with coequalizers, see maps out of for the variety of abelian groups seen as an ordinary category—this would be a lot like asking the forgetful functor to commute with coequalizers, when really it probably only commutes with quotients of equivalence relations.