You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Hello!
My name is Adam and I am trying to get back up to speed with category theory after a ~5 year hiatus.
image.png
A friend of mine has shared his problem sets for a course to help me practice and I wonder if anyone would be willing to ... evaluate... (which isn't to say grade) some of my solutions.
I am also very rusty with LaTeX formatting and proof styling in general, so I welcome feedback about those as well.
Am I on the right track for these 3-for-2 cases?
Is there a better setup for 'equational' reasoning?
What you wrote makes sense to me! (Edit: I thought I spotted a mistake, but upon reading more carefully, it looks correct to me!)
This all looks good so far! Hopefully you've noticed that this is only a solution to part of the statement.
I wouldn't be quite so persnickety about the formatting and justifying each equational transformation explicitly. Mathematicians actually write in paragraphs and this is often much better for understanding the core ideas of something you're working on than this laborious two-column proof format. I might rewrite your argument somewhat like this:
Suppose are isomorphisms, with inverses Then we claim Indeed, we have and which establishes the claim.
Notice that I haven't explicitly said where I'm using the definition of the inverse of a morphism, or even restated what that definition is. You could add either of these, but it's the only thing I could possibly be using here so it's quite standard not to insist on highlighting it. This is a simple enough argument that it's counterproductive to make a big meal of it.
If I were to try and prove this, I would also consider proving some general things first, so that each of the three cases can be proved using a quicker argument. (But this is a matter of personal preference!)
Regarding LaTex, I really enjoy using Obsidian for typing up my (informal) math notes. I find it a lot faster and easier than using something like Overleaf.
Thank your both for your replies.
Yes, I know I have two other cases to cover for the entire 3-for-2, where $g \circ f$, is assumed to be iso. For each, one of L/R inverse is fast but I am having some more trouble with the other.
I confess that Lemmon-style natural deduction proofs, and mathematical logic in general, is what sparked my love for pure mathematics, so I have a penchant for 'explicit' and 'laborious' proofs. :sweat_smile:
It's one way that I try to ensure my derivations are rigorous, but I know also that it becomes unsustainable pretty quickly.
This is also my first time using Zulip; would it be okay for me to upload images of 'hand-written' solutions?
I write them with a stylus on a tablet before transferring them to Overleaf.
Here is what I meant about one side being trickier than the other
For this case the fact that it is a right inverse is immediate... but I am not sure how to show the left inverse.
Have I even chosen the right morphisms?
There are so few these seem like the only candidates!
Here is what I came up with, and I suppose even I am now feeling the tedium of the 'one substitution at a time' equational reasoning :sweat_smile:
image.png
That looks alright to me, as far as I can tell after looking through it quickly!
To make things less laborious, you might find it interesting to prove these two things, which can help enable a quicker proof (I believe):
If we accept (or prove!) these two things, here's how one way to quickly prove that is an isomorphism if and are:
David,
Thank you again for your responses!
The first case I proved (in the first image) shows that ‘composing two isos is iso’ correct?
For the second result, if we do not specify R/L inverse, we mean it is both, correct?
That is ‘the inverse of an iso is iso’ means ‘the (two-sided) inverse of an iso is iso?’
I ask mostly because the very next exercise requires me to distinguish carefully between right and left inverses
You are welcome!
Yes, I think you showed above that if and are isomorphisms, then is an isomorphism. So, composing two isomorphisms gives us an isomorphism.
Regarding left and right inverses, for to be an isomorphism, it has to have a two-sided inverse. For example, in "Category Theory in Context", Riehl defines an isomorphism like this "An isomorphism in a category is a morphism for which there exists a morphism so that and ."
In addition, if an isomorphism has a left (or right) inverse , that one-sided inverse is actually a two sided inverse! (So ). A proof is given on the nLab: here. You might also find it interesting to prove this.
This last point (that left inverses of iso are also right inverses, and therefore iso) is one of the exercises!
While thinking about such things it's fun to find the smallest category that has a morphism that has a left inverse that is not its right inverse. It only need to have one object. How many morphisms does it need to have?
(Just throwing this out there in case anyone wants to think more about left vs. right inverses.)
I'm not sure I would call the solution you're hinting at the "smallest one" :smiley:
Right by ‘small’ do we only mean the size of the class of objects?
The way you phrase it, and Jonas’ response make me think many morphisms are necessary… :sweat_smile:
Also, we mean an abstract category, and just some morphism equations?
Or is the example a concrete category where the single object has internal structure beyond its morphisms?
By "small" I meant having the fewest objects and/or morphisms - not a very precise condition, but we'll probably recognize the winner when we see it! I slipped and suggested using one object, but I guess Jonas is hinting that then we inevitably get lots of morphisms.
Maybe I'll give some more hints. Let's try a category with objects and , and morphisms and such that is the left inverse of :
but not the right inverse:
If we go this route, what's the minimum number of morphisms our category can have?
I think there is a bigger problem with the one-object "smallest one" than the "smallest" part.
Unless any of us are telepathic or have a side channel to John, I don't think we can know which one-object category he had in mind. There certainly exist one-object categories containing such a morphism. I don't know offhand whether there are any finite ones, but at least there's an initial one (which I think is infinite) which has some claim to be called the "smallest".
I don't think there are any finite examples. It would have to be a finite monoid with a section-retraction pair. But then left multiplication by the section would be an injective function from a finite set to itself, and then...
I may be confused, but I thought any one-object category can be viewed as a group, where the morphisms of the category are the group elements, and the composition of morphisms is group multiplication. I'm pretty sure inverses in a group are always two-sided.
A monoid, not a group.
John Baez said:
Maybe I'll give some more hints. Let's try a category with objects and , and morphisms and such that is the left inverse of :
but not the right inverse:
@Adam Millar focus on this version ;)
Right, my thought of making was a last-minute extra twist that I soon came to regret. Focus on this version, everyone.
Thank you all for your responses.
I have my solution to
"If has a left inverse that is iso, then is also iso;
image.png
This is my next point of attack.
if but ,
We are asking 'how many (other?) morphisms are necessary to make this true?'
Or, put another way, if what DOES
Morgan Rogers (he/him) said:
John Baez said:
Maybe I'll give some more hints. Let's try a category with objects and , and morphisms and such that is the left inverse of :
but not the right inverse:
Adam Millar focus on this version ;)
Also, I made this proof.
image.png
Great! I'm beginning to want you to tackle my puzzle (the version Morgan Rogers recommended), because in addition to proving theorems it's crucial to learn how to find examples and counterexamples. Theorems are about generality, but examples force you to master specificity.
Even if all you want to do in life is prove theorems, finding counterexamples is crucial, because they tell you when some would-be theorem is actually false, or when a hoped-for proof can't work. This can save you lots of time.
John Baez said:
Great! I'm beginning to want you to tackle my puzzle (the version Morgan Rogers recommended), because in addition to proving theorems it's crucial to learn how to find examples and counterexamples. Theorems are about generality, but examples force you to master specificity.
Oh John, you are a man after my own heart.
Even right now, in my 'intro to proof-based math' course for first year undergrads, I use almost exactly this language when exploring new topics with students.
First we make a general claim, then try to prove it wrong (produce a counterexample).
The counterexample reveals what further assumptions might be necessary to make the theorem follow in generality
To use a very basic example;
Claim; If n is divisible by 4 then it is divisible by 12.
Counterexample; If n=16 then 4|n but not 12|n
... what went wrong with 16?
Ah, it isn't divisible by 3!
Ok so THEOREM: If 4|n AND 3|n then 12|n