You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
This is not a question.
Here I am answering a side quest from @David Egolf 's thread.
Puzzle: Show that the étale space associated with the sheaf of analytic functions on is also Hausdorff.
The topology on is generated by the following base of open subsets. Given with an open subset of , and a section of the analytic sheaf, define to be the set of germs for all . An open set is is an arbitrary union of these basic open sets.
Let be two distinct points of . I.e., (resp. ) is the germ at (resp. ) of some analytic function (resp. ) with an open domain (resp. )
First, consider the case . Because is Hausdorff, there exists two open subsets $U', V'$ such that
Let (resp. ) be the open subset of associated to the restriction of (resp. ) to (resp. ). Then
Let , and
Those sets are open neighbourhoods of and respectively.
We claim that . Assume, by contradiction, that there exists a germ . This means that and have a common germ at some point .
In particular, and have the same power series at
Because and are analytic functions, this implies that they agree on some open subset of . Moreover, the unicity of analytic continuation implies that and actually agree over . Hence
But we assumed and to be distinct, whence a contradiction.
The crux of the argument seems to rely on the fact that, for every point , the map
is injective.
Now, I am wondering if this injectiveness characterizes the Hausdorff property.
Let's consider an arbitrary sheaf over , for which there is a way to make sense of the 's (e.g., maybe a sub-sheaf of some sheaf of distributions).
Can we prove that the proposition " is Hausdorff" is equivalent to "the 's are all injective"?
The only problem with proving a general proposition like that is that for an arbitrary sheaf on we don't have any natural way to define the functions. We could try to study which sheaves do have such functions, and then try to prove the proposition you want. But I think there's a necessary and sufficient condition for to be Hausdorff which is very general, simple to state, and easy to prove! It's this:
Conjecture. Suppose is sheaf on a topological space . Then is Hausdorff if and only if for every open and every , the set of points for which the germ of equals the germ of is closed in .
I'm calling it a conjecture because I haven't checked it, but a special case is proved here.
In the case where is the sheaf of analytic functions on , we use the conjecture by showing that for any two analytic functions defined on some open set , the set on which their germs are equal is closed in . The conjecture then implies is Hausdorff.
In the case where is the sheaf of smooth functions on , we use the conjecture by finding two smooth functions on for which the set on which their germs are equal is not closed. We can use the function and the function
We can check that these two functions have equal germs at for , but different germs for .
The conjecture then implies that is not Hausdorff.
This proposition is way more neat, indeed!
Here is a proof (I think).
Assume is Hausdorff. Let
We show that is open. Fix . Since is Hausdorff, there exists two disjoint open subsets such that
By definition of the topology on , this implies that there exists open neighborhoods of such that
The last condition further implies that
In other words, . I.e., is open.
Assume that for any open subset , for any sections , the set is open. We prove that is Hausdorff.
Fix two germs and in , and assume that they are distinct, .
If , then, since is Hausdorff, there exists two disjoint open subsets containing and respectively. Then
Because and are disjoint, these open sets are also disjoint.
Assume now that . Let . Then . Since is open, there exists an open neighborhood of . Then
and, by definition of , these two open subsets of are disjoint.
Therefore, is Hausdorff.
I think my wanderings about analytic functions and stuff is due to the fact that I was trying to capture the argument "if a property is true at some point , then it is true on a neighborhood of ".
But this is actually pure topology: this argument is true exactly when the subset characterized by is open w.r.t to the topology of .
Peva Blanchard said:
What does this notation mean?
My guess is that means the open set in given by the set of all the germs of when it is restricted to . So, I guess that it is what I've been calling .
Yes, David is right.