You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Given monads , I'm pretty sure that there is a theorem saying that
distributive laws
monad structures on which are compatible with the monad structures on and in a suitable way
"liftings" of to the category , of -algebras
"extensions" of to the Kleisli category
are all equivalent.
Beck's original article "Distributive Laws" and Barr/Well's "Toposes, Triples, and Theories" show the equivalence of 1--3, but don't mention 4 as far as I can see.
Does anybody know where to find a statement of the "full" theorem including 4?
Hm, I thought I knew a reference but it seems like it's generally taken for granted. There's an abstract proof using the formal theory of monads, thinking of as the initial left -module, and pasting with the distributive law. But the down-to-earth reasoning:
given a Kleisli morphism , what structure is necessary to apply ? We have , and then we need a natural transformation to define . The laws for are exactly what you need for this extension of to to be functorial.
I can keep looking for a reference. Surely someone has written it up.
Yeah it's strange because I see works, such as https://arxiv.org/pdf/2007.12982.pdf Distributive Laws for Relative Monads, which say that the original Beck article includes the equivalence with Kleisli extensions, but I don't see it in there. However the former paper makes it seem like it's been accepted by experts that the formal theory of monads gives a fully general and sufficient theorem of this equivalence - though it might not be spelled out very explicitly there.
That's funny ! I'm also confused where I know the statement from, if not from Barr/Wells, which I read as a student. Barr and Wells have a nice triangle diagram on page 264, which visualizes the equivalence of 1--3, and notably leaves out Kleisli categories.
Proposition 5.2.5 in Bart Jacobs' Introduction to Coalgebra shows the correspondence between extensions of a functor to the Kleisli category and distributive laws of the functor over the monad (two diagrams are missing from the usual monad distributive law), then they mention in the exercises that you can make this about monads only.
This topic was moved here from #general > distributive laws by [Mod] Morgan Rogers
Theorem 4.26 of Tanaka's thesis Pseudo-Distributive Laws and a Unified Framework for Variable Binding contains the equivalence of 1, 3 and 4. It also follows from Corollary 6.20 of Distributive laws for relative monads. However, I don't think I've seen an explicit reference to 2 outside of Beck's paper (I have also looked for a unified statement in the past and been unable to find one).
Ralph Sarkis said:
Proposition 5.2.5 in Bart Jacobs' Introduction to Coalgebra shows the correspondence between extensions of a functor to the Kleisli category and distributive laws of the functor over the monad
ahh that's a good point that it works w/o the monad structure on the lifted functor. at this level of generality it should be precisely the universal property of the Kleisli category viewed as a lax colimit.
Nathanael Arkor said:
Theorem 4.26 of Tanaka's thesis Pseudo-Distributive Laws and a Unified Framework for Variable Binding contains the equivalence of 1, 3 and 4.
Ahh that's pretty close, thanks.
I don't think I've seen an explicit reference to 2 outside of Beck's paper (I have also looked for a unified statement in the past and been unable to find one).
Barr and Wells reproduce precisely Beck's statement, with the advantage of better readability since they write compositions in the conventional way. I guess I'm just wondering why they didn't include the statement about Kleisli categories, since the Kleisli and EM-constructions and their relation are discussed at great length in the book.
For monads on an object in a 2-category , an extension of to in is the same as a lifting of to in . So since the proof is purely diagrammatic and works in any 2-category, the equivalence with (3) implies the equivalence with (4). (Note that a distributive law in becomes a distributive law in .)