You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Many of you who had to tolerate my stubborness lately, know that I've been interested in "differential 2-rigs" https://arxiv.org/abs/2103.00938; now, mostly thanks to the fact that @Todd Trimble joined @Fabrizio Genovese and me, the work has almost doubled in length, and many other interesting ideas emerged.
As you can see, the paper ends with an account of "future prospects"; one the ideas is to study differential equations in a 2-rig. Let me sketch the main lines of the discussion.
Given a 2-rig with a derivation, it is a natural question to investigate the fixed points of a derivation on , when is regarded as an endofunctor, if by 'fixed point' we mean an initial algebra or a terminal coalgebra of .
One could legitimately call an such that a 'Napier object', (for the obvious reason that 'exponential object' already has a different meaning).
Now, given that preserves coproducts, initial -algebras are seldom an interesting object; the initial chain
needed to build the initial -algebra stops after a single step.
On the other hand, terminal colgebras turn out to be linked to the behaviour of the object : the terminal cochain is
thus the first ordinal for which the transition morphism is invertible realises the terminal coalgebra. This is related to an old question of mine, where I was asking what's up with , and whether I can expect it to be zero just as a consequence of the axioms.
Now, it takes just a little bit of imagination to zoom-out from this particular instance of a fixed point to speak of the following in a 2-rig with duals: if we interpret the word 'solution' to mean 'terminal coalgebra', then we can define also
This paves the way to the following
Definition (Differential-polynomial equation). A (ordinary) differential-polynomial equation (DPE for short) is (slightly informally, the paper gives a better definition) a functor that can be obtained from iterate composition of 'polynomial operations' (sum and product) and derivation.
An example of a DPEs 'with constant coefficients' is
a solution for a given DPE consists of a terminal coalgebra for , regarded as an endofunctor of . Clearly, a Napier object is a solution for the DPE , whereas a hyperbolic sine object is a solution for .
Now, let's switch to the theory of differential equations in the category of species; it has a long history; first introduced in the initial works by Joyal, it was mostly developed by Leroux and Viennot, Labelle, Rajan...
My claim now is that the general theory of combinatorial differential equations studied in these papers might be framed into a more general theory of DPEs and their solutions. As far as I understand, no one attempted to develop this general theory of DPEs in a differential 2-rig. And determining the 'solutions' of a DPE in species has always been a matter of hard group theory (see e.g. the work of Rajan on the solutions of ), hard combinatorics (see various papers by Labelle) or clever manipulations only valid in special cases.
In fact, a remarkable theorem of Labelle says that a given ODE in species can have distinct solutions for every , except . Now, among these solutions, by definition, there must be the terminal coalgebra for the endofunctor that defines the ODE, and my claim is that that universal object deserves the name of "the solution" of the ODE.
A remarkable example of this multiplicity of solutions lives in the category of virtual species (more or less, formal differences of species, like one would do in a cancellative monoid to obtain its Grothendieck group); there, we can solve all combinatorial differential equations where is a given species: its general solution is of the form where is a solution of , and
where is the species of -element sets, and ; it just takes the Leibniz rule to prove that in fact .
An enticing piece of the theory of combinatorial species that might turn out to be useful in order to attack the study of DPEs relies on the results outlined by Rajan in "The adjoints to the derivative functor on species".
The upshot of the paper is that the good behaviour of the derivative functor on species can be at least partly motivated with the fact that sits in a triple of adjoints
This is somewhat a cheap observation for a category theorist: happens to be defined as pre-composition with the 'add 1' functor on the category of sets and bijections; thus, its left (resp., right) adjoint is nothing more than the left (resp., right) Kan extension along :
The observation has, however, deep consequences.
More conceptually, one can see that results as the functor , where is the internal hom of the Day convolution monoidal structure; thus
since is representable, hence a tiny object of , the functor is also cocontinuous, hence a left adjoint by the adjoint functor theorem; its right adjoint is a functor that we denote , and that coincides with .
Explicit formulas for and can be easily computed:
Being able to jump between one of these descriptions and another turns out to be useful in computations, and provides explicit formulas for in case is the characteristic species of -tuples, a representable species, the terminal species, the species of powerset...
This suggests that the study of differential equations in the category of species can be developed to a certain extent in order to obtain combinatorial equations in terms of polynomial expressions in the endofunctors .
The only missing piece in order to carry on this analysis is a precise description of how the monads and the comonads generated by the triple of adjoints above interact with each other and split as composition of simpler functors:
Proposition. Let be the 'tautological' species sending a finite set to itself. Let be the identity functor on the category of species. Then,
1. , as it follows from the computation
2. sending a species to the species (proof: a straightforward, similar manipulation); similarly,
3. , sending a species to the species ;
4. , sending a species to the species .
This formalism is rather powerful: for example, it can prove by completely formal means the isomorphism between the species of powersets and the two-fold convolution of the terminal species.
Another remarkable result on the structure of the category of species was due to Yeh (afaicu, a student of Labelle) whose doctoral thesis "On the Combinatorial Species of Joyal" proved the following: let's call a species a molecule if it is indecomposable with respect to coproduct, and an atom if it is indecomposable with respect to product.
It's easy to see that a molecule is concentrated at a single cardinality of those 's for which is nonempty, i.e. for every other whose cardinality is not ; the number so determined is the degree of the molecule.
Every species can be uniquely written as a sum of molecules (in fact, as a sum of its molecular sub-species), and every molecule can be uniquely written as a product of atoms.
Then, we have the following
Theorem (Yeh decomposition). The rig of isomorphism classes of species is isomorphic to the rig of polynomials with natural coefficients, on a countably infinite set of indeterminates that can be taken to form an ordered enumeration of its atoms:
Evidently, the definition of molecule and atom transports in a straightforward way to the case of general 2-rigs. This leads to the following definition.
Definition (Scopic 2-rig). A 2-rig is called scopic if it has a countable set of atoms , and
where is an enumeration of , and is a suitably define 'free 2-rig' with coefficients in .
In addition, in there is just a finite set of molecules of a given degree; in fact, Yeh proves the following: is equal to the number of conjugacy classes of subgroups of the symmetric group on elements, and there is an explicit procedure to build all the molecules of a given degree. As a side remark, this suggests that there exists a very tight connection between the theory of differential equations over and the representation theory of symmetric groups; this tight connection reflects on the theory of differential equations, and a remarkable example of this connection is the main result in Rajan.
In a general 2-rig the notion of degree does not seem to make sense.
Whew, this was a long trip.
Now, my question is: is it possible to find nontrivial examples of scopic 2-rigs, other than the 2-rig of species?
That was great, @fosco! I love species so it's nice to see more about them.
Now, my question is: is it possible to find nontrivial examples of scopic 2-rigs, other than the 2-rig of species?
Species are presheaves on the groupoid of finite sets, and the category of species has a few interesting 2-rig structures, at least in my favorite definition of '2-rig': a symmetric monoidal cocomplete category where tensor product distributes over colimits.
My favorite 2-rig structure on species is the one you're calling : Day convolution with respect to the "disjoint union" monoidal structure on the groupoid of finite sets.
I wish there was an briefer way to distinguish different sorts of 2-rigs in a consistent and clear way.
But the definition of "atomic" species uses products and coproducts, so maybe you (Fosco) are talking about 2-rigs where the monoidal structure is cartesian product!
And of course species also becomes a 2-rig in this way, where the monoidal structure is cartesian product.
Anyway, while I'm confused about your definition of 2-rig, I can try to give some examples of scopic 2-rigs.
What features of a category make the category of presheaves on into a scopic 2-rig?
If we use the 2-rig structure where the monoidal structure is the cartesian product, then of course the category of presheaves on any category becomes a 2-rig.
So then the question is just when this is "scopic".
Here's my guess about some sufficient conditions on : it may suffice for to be a groupoid that's a countable coproduct of 1-object groupoids, each coming from a finite group.
After all, that seemed to be the key to proving that when is the groupoid of finite sets, presheaves on form a scopic 2-rig.
If my guess is right, there are tons of nice examples of . For example, the groupoid of finite-dimensional vector spaces over a finite field. Or the groupoid of finite graphs!
@John Baez I remember there was a bit of confusion some time ago, when I started studying this stuff, about the def of "2-rig"
Let me dispel your confusion: I want to study a "differential 2-rig": a category endowed with two monoidal structures, one of which is cocartesian, and over which another monoidal structure distributes; and moreover, there is a functor D : C -> C that preserves coproducts and satisfies the Leibniz rule.
This notion of 2-rig is less general in some respect (the additive structure is cocartesian, not a generic monoidal structure): this makes easier to work without all the coherence Laplaza needs
It is also more general: I don't want the multiplicative structure to distribute over all colimits; "being linear" means "commuting with coproducts"
Okay, so I'd say your 2-rigs are monoidal categories with finite coproducts, where the tensor product distributes over coproducts.
precisely
These are a bit more general than my favorite definition of 2-rig: a monoidal category with small colimits, where the tensor product distributes over colimits.
But I actually consider many different variants for different reasons, so if finite coproducts is all you need, that's fine with me.
it makes things work; I've been open for a long time to the possibility that some nontrivial examples of derivation live outside this framework.
I still am
My other big question concerns this: your definition of "scopic" seemed to make use of products.
I.e., cartesian products.
So I was a bit confused, since your definition of 2-rig doesn't seem to require products.
(There's something we could call a "cartesian 2-rig" where the monoidal structure is cartesian product.)
uh, no; that part was a bit confused (not only because of this): the operation that I called product is Cauchy product of species, not Hadamard product of species
Hadamard product = cartesian
Cauchy = Day convolution
at least judging from the literature...
That's indeed how the terminology goes.
So a species is molecular if it's not a coproduct in a nontrivial way, and then atomic if it's not a Cauchy product in a nontrivial way? I've read about this but I tend to forget...
Anyway, if atomicity is defined with respect to the Cauchy product (in the case of species), I'll revise my conjecture about how to get piles of "scopic 2-rigs", though the two concrete examples I mentioned will still be on my list!
it's gettin late in Europe, I'll be back tomorrow. But I'm glad I generated some discussion
Okay, great. If you answer my question tomorrow I'll try to give you piles of scopic 2-rigs.
Yeh was a student of Steve Schanuel in Buffalo, but then he went on to a postdoc position in Montréal.
Who is "he"? This has been a long conversation.
Yeh :-)
(pronouns: ye/yim)
[typing...]
I am a bit confused about Yeh's decomposition theorem, and I suspect it has to do with some representation theory of the symmetric groups, and that maybe it is an artifact of working over sets.
Over groupoids I think it would look like this, and it is not nearly as interesting as Yeh's theorem. (And maybe I am just misunderstanding everything.)
Likke most mathematics it's an artifact of working over sets.
Every G-set is a coproduct of transitive G-sets, and any transitive G-set is of the form G/H for some subgroup H of G.
This lets you decompose any presheaf on a groupoid as a coproduct of pieces that can't be further decomposed this way.
Namely, every groupoid X is equivalent to a coproduct of connected groupoids, which come from groups , and then every presheaf on X is just a coproduct of ones of the form .
I believe this is what they call the "molecular decomposition" of a species, when X is the groupoid of finite sets.
Groupoid-valued species (also called stuff types) are the same thing as finitary polynomial functors over groupoids, meaning functors represented by a map of groupoids E -> B with finite discrete fibres. The equivalence goes like this: there is a classifier for finite sets, given by BB' -> BB where BB is the groupoid of finite sets and bijections, and BB' is the groupoid of finite pointed sets and basepoint preserving bijections. Since it is a classifier, any map E -> B induces a map B -> BB. That's essentially a species: you can extract a species by taking F: BB -> Grpd to be the functor sending n to the homotopy fibre over n. Conversely, given a species F: BB -> Grpd, take the Grothendieck construction to get something over BB, say B -> BB and then pullback the universal family to get something over B.
This is nice, because now the polynomial functor defined by E -> B is the analytic functor defined by the corresponding species F. The point is that over groupoids there is no distinction between finitary polynomial and analytic. The bad group-action quotients that screwed up this equivalence over the category of sets become well behaved over groupoids, where it is as if every group action is free.
Now the Cauchy product is just product of functors, and sums are sums. And polynomial functors obviously form a polynomial ring...
But I guess the point is that the sums involved in the definition of polynomial functors over groupoids are rather homotopy sums. That just means colimits over groupoids (just like ordinary sums are colimits over discrete sets). If these fancier sums are allowed, then
OK, meanwhile John explained it, now I think I understand: if you allow homotopy sums instead of just discrete sums, then it seems that the molecules are the monomials and the only atom is X, because X^n is obviously the product of n copies of X. So the subtlety is that only discrete sums are allowed in the definition of molecule, and then there are many more of them, namely all the G/H John mentioned.
I think the definition of atom in species theory is different than the one you're using, because I think there's not just one atom.
I just seem to recall (from the Big Red Book of Species) that there are lots of atomic species.
But I don't really understand the definition of atomic species, even though Fosco just tried to explain it a while back.
Yes, I agree that most mathematics is an artifact of working over sets :-)
Yes, the notion of atom I was using is too simplistic. It just shifts all the representation theory into the notion of sums, and does probably not help at all.
Okay, I looked it up, though Fosco actually said it earlier:
A species is molecular if it can't be written as a coproduct of other species in a nontrivial way, and it's atomic if it's molecular and it can't be written as a Cauchy product of other species in a nontrivial way.
(The Cauchy product is the Day convolution product with respect to the "disjoint union" monoidal structure on the groupoid of finite sets.)
So what you were calling X, "being a one-element set", is atomic, but there are other atomic species.
Ah, the Burnside ring!
It looks like after Proposition 5.1 they claim that whenever is a transitive subgroup of , i.e. one whose obvious action on the n-element set is transitive, it gives an atomic species.
Unfortunately I bet that's not an "if and only if".
Yes, I was being silly: the other atomic species become homotopy sums of the one-element-set species, since any group action quotient counts as a homotopy sum. So with homotopy sums there is no interesting notion of atom.
John Baez said:
Unfortunately I bet that's not an "if and only if".
I'm back.
It's not, but we know what we're identifying: two conjugate transitive subgroups give the same molecule
I see you have already mentioned Yeh's theorem about the Burnside ring
Today I have a question I've been discussing with @Todd Trimble and others, a purely combinatorial curiosity.
The way in which you build the terminal coalgebra for an endofunctor is "apply the functor to 1 a sufficient amount of times". If we do this for seemingly innocuous differential equations we find interesting recurrence relations:
the coefficients of these expressions seem to be some multinomials (35, 70, 105.. appear in https://oeis.org/A080575)
If you play the same game with the differential operator , starting from , you get , and , and , etc.:
The solution of the differential equation is not so immediate to find, but with some Weyl-algebra sorcery you get that
in the ring of power series, taking into account the fact that , and in fact finding a "nice" closed form for the iterated powers of
Joe Moeller said:
I wish there was an briefer way to distinguish different sorts of 2-rigs in a consistent and clear way.
A naming or notation system would be handy.
Morgan Rogers (he/him) said:
Joe Moeller said:
I wish there was an briefer way to distinguish different sorts of 2-rigs in a consistent and clear way.
A naming or notation system would be handy.
This was discussed extensively in the other thread. There are consistent names for each of these concepts, but "2-rig" is shorter, so people tend to overload it.
[xkcd_standards.jpeg]
I'm guilty, alas!
Now that I know what "scopic 2-rig", I think I can give @fosco a shitload of scopic 2-rigs. But I'm not going to prove anything here, just conjecture stuff.
My claimed scopic 2-rigs will be of this form: the category of presheaves on a groupoid , made monoidal via Day convolution with respect to some monoidal structure on .
The classic example to keep in mind is when is the groupoid of finite sets and bijections, made monoidal using disjoint union. By the way, disjoint union is not coproduct in , but it is the coproduct in a larger category containing , namely the category of finite sets and functions. We can take the coproduct monoidal structure on and restrict it to to get a monoidal structure on .
All my other claimed examples of scopic 2-rig will have the same general flavor; in particular the groupoid will always be the core of some category with finite coproducts, and will get its monoidal structure that way.
Here are some examples of :
What do these have in common, that makes with Day convolution be scopic?
First of all, every object of has a finite group of automorphisms.
This guarantees that is equivalent to a coproduct of finite groups - or, more pedantically, the coproduct of 1-object groupoids that are deloopings of finite groups.
Second of all, there are countably many isomorphism classes of objects in . This is because @fosco had a countability condition in his definition of "scopic".
Third, is -graded in the following sense: each object has a grade , such that
And fourth, has finitely many isomorphism classes of objects in each grade. (The third and fourth conditions actually imply the second.)
In my categories of graphs, the grade of a graph is its number of vertices. In the category of vector spaces, the grade of a vector space is its dimension.
We don't actually need to be -graded; it could be -graded, but there are already lots of -graded examples.
So that's my conjecture: if is a category with finite coproducts obeying conditions 1)-4), and is its core, then is scopic.
If this conjecture is wrong, it could easily be because I don't fully grok @fosco's definition of "scopic", or Yeh's theorem. What my conditions 1)-4) are really supposed to imply is this:
Every object of can be uniquely written as a coproduct of molecules (objects that cannot be further decomposed as coproducts in a nontrivial way), and every molecule can be uniquely written as a tensor product of atoms (molecules that cannot be further decomposed as tensor products in a nontrivial way).
@John Baez : I will soon get back at you. Unfortunately the different timezones we're in make the conversation a bit asyncronous.
Yup!
This topic was moved by Nathanael Arkor to #learning: questions > All about 2-rigs: should they be called 2-rigs?