You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
I was trying to better understand Grothendieck fibrations and I came up with this characterisation of cartesian morphisms which I thought was nice; I'm wondering if it's part of some more general story that I'm unaware of.
Let be a functor. Say that an object of is terminal relative to if the following are true:
This is a “fibred” version of the definition of terminal object, in the sense that an object of is terminal if and only if it is terminal relative to the unique functor .
Then
Claim. A morphism is -cartesian if and only if it a terminal object relative to .
So is a Grothendieck fibration iff for all , all objects of admit a -terminal lift to .
As it is this is just a “cute” rephrasing, but it made me wonder -- is there a general story about “fibred limits” of which this is an instance? The nLab didn't help.
It's probably related to the characterisation of fibrations in terms of adjoints and comma categories, and of adjoints in terms of initial/terminal objects...
By inverse image, a functor is equivalent to a (normal) lax functor . It is a fibration when each is representable as cart-rep.png
So I think this pertains to the equivalence of representation and terminal objects, which then comes up in the concept of fibrations.
I was about to write something similar: a functor is representable if and only if its category of elements has an initial/terminal object (depending on the variance of )
This stackexchange question by a certain @fosco seems to suggest that representability of a profunctor is not equivalent to a “bare” initiality/terminality condition on the category of elements.
At this point I would conjecture that it could, instead, be equivalent to initiality/terminality relative to one end of the two-sided discrete fibration, as in my definition?
In any case, my question is not so much about fibrations, as it is about this “universality relative to a functor” definition, which happens to have cartesian morphisms as an instance.
It seems to me that there is a clear generalisation to “fibred limits” of each shape (just replace “objects” with “cocones” and “morphisms” with “morphisms of cocones”). I would like to know if the theory of these things has been worked out somewhere.
Amar Hadzihasanovic said:
At this point I would conjecture that it could, instead, be equivalent to initiality/terminality relative to one end of the two-sided discrete fibration, as in my definition?
To make this more precise: consider a profunctor . To this we can associate a two-sided fibration , , where is a discrete opfibration and a discrete fibration.
Then:
Conjecture. is representable as if and only if has a terminal object relative to , and is representable as if and only if has an initial object relative to .
Update: no, this seems all wrong.
I may have gotten some variances wrong, but I think this reduces to the usual condition for representability of (co)presheaves when either or is trivial.
Amar Hadzihasanovic said:
This stackexchange question by a certain fosco seems to suggest that representability of a profunctor is not equivalent to a “bare” initiality/terminality condition on the category of elements.
At this point I would conjecture that it could, instead, be equivalent to initiality/terminality relative to one end of the two-sided discrete fibration, as in my definition?
I know the guy, you shouldn't trust him :stuck_out_tongue:
This is why I didn't write anything in the end, I didn't know how to relate the two things precisely, given that result :frown: incidentally it is related to the annoying fact that the collage of two categorie along a profunctor is not the cat of elements of the profunctor
for a profunctor regarded as a presheaf over representability is a splitting into two Yoneda's
Instead what you want is a profunctor whose transposed is objectwise representable
(also, I will gladly talk about this tomorrow in person, now I really am too tired to say something meaningful!)
but hmu with developments, this is interesting and I thought a lot about how to see basic facts of fibered categories for a generic displayed category
ah, you left me with a nice toy before bed!
If are discrete categories a profunctor is a matrix of sets, and is representable if and only if the matrix is made only of 0s and 1s (or rather, 's and 's) and each row has exactly one 1 (I hope I didn't transpose the matrix I'm considering...)
this means that there is a function such that
and is 1 if and only if , 0 otherwise
can you relate this to your conjecture?
We can try to figure it out tomorrow or Friday, I'm off to bed now :D
same! :grinning:
(Not in bed obviously) on second thought I don't think my conjecture makes sense, in this case you need fibrewise terminal/initial objects which is different from what “fibred” terminal is
I.e. I think for profunctors the condition for e.g. representability as is that, for in , each fiber has a terminal object, which is very different from having a terminal object rel ...
Section 4.3.1 of Higher Topos Theory on relative colimits might be related.
Amar Hadzihasanovic said:
I.e. I think for profunctors the condition for e.g. representability as is that, for in , each fiber has a terminal object, which is very different from having a terminal object rel ...
Ah, perhaps this works:
Revised conjecture. is representable as if and only if every in lifts to a terminal object in relative to , and is representable as if and only if every in lifts to an initial object in relative to .
Taichi Uemura said:
Section 4.3.1 of Higher Topos Theory on relative colimits might be related.
I will take a look, thank you!
Ok so after in-person discussion with Fosco I think we have figured out the following.
Given , the property that “every object of has a lift to that is terminal relative to ” is equivalent to “ has a fully faithful right adjoint”, so this recovers an equivalent definition of fibrations (according to Fosco, due to Chevalley): is a Grothendieck fibration iff for all , the functor has a fully faithful right adjoint.
And now, maybe we should be able to also answer my “revised conjecture”: we have that, given the graph of a profunctor , the condition that every lifts to a -terminal object of is equivalent to having a fully faithful right adjoint, i.e. exhibiting as a reflective subcategory of
Which sounds very much like the answer to the SE question mentioned above, if we accept that maybe the collage of a profunctor was mixed-up with the graph of a profunctor
(The result is quoted in Gray's "Fibered and cofibered categories", where Gray attributes it to Chevalley, and the fibrations you get are only the cloven ones; see also the Monoidal toplogy book)
(Unless maybe there's also a dual characterisation in terms of reflective subcategories of the collage, which may well be)
Christian Williams said:
By inverse image, a functor is equivalent to a (normal) lax functor . It is a fibration when each is representable as
It's just a prefibration then though, right? For a fibration it needs to be a pseudofunctor as well.
(Sorry if this has already been mentioned, I've only skimmed the rest of the discussion so far)
Amar Hadzihasanovic said:
Given , the property that “every object of has a lift to that is terminal relative to ” is equivalent to “ has a fully faithful right adjoint”, so this recovers an equivalent definition of fibrations (according to Fosco, due to Chevalley): is a Grothendieck fibration iff for all , the functor has a fully faithful right adjoint.
Well, I am not sure this story is exactly as described above. Let me say that Theorem 2.10 on Gray's 1966 paper states (among other things, and adapting the notation) that your functor is a fibration iff for each , has a rari, i.e. a right adjoint right inverse. Now, if I am not wrong, this condition is slightly stronger than having a fully faithful right adjoint, because in the first case the counit is an identity, while in the second one it is just an iso. However, the picture from the Monoidal Topology book provided by @fosco is correct, since it asks for the counit to be an identity.
Concerning Chevalley, this is another bit of the same story.
It is true that Gray mentions some handwritten notes of a seminar given by Chevalley at Berkley in 1962 - i.e. some three/four years before his paper. What he says, however, is that such notes "treated these questions from a slightly different point of view". Then, he points the reader to Proposition 3.11, where he claims to discuss the "Chevalley condition". Therefore, I do not see any reason to credit Theorem 2.10 to Chevalley. As far as I understand, such result is of Gray himself.
On there other hand, there exists this Chevalley criterion, which is stated in Proposition 3.11. It says that a functor as above is a fibration iff the canonical comparison functor has a rari. Notice that such a condition is stated globally, while that of Theorem 2.10 is a collection of local conditions.
More details on Chevalley, with some care to the internal (formal) aspects can be found on a paper of mine (and coauthors):
This is indeed a final cut.
You can find the arxived version v1 (https://arxiv.org/pdf/1909.10822v1.pdf), which, together with some mistakes corrected in the final version, contains (in the appendix) the explicit proof of the internal version of the Chevalley criterion.
Thanks, yes, I was being a bit careless with the rari / reflective subcategory / fully faithful right adjoint distinction!
Don't worry! It took me ages to get this point!
If it helps, slice-wise ff right adjoints give Street fibrations.