Category Theory
Zulip Server
Archive

You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.


Stream: theory: category theory

Topic: Fiber object


view this post on Zulip Jean-Baptiste Vienney (Jan 04 2025 at 22:54):

Has this notion been studied? Is it a special case of a known concept?

Let C\mathcal{C} be a category together with a distinguished object C\top \in \mathcal{C} (typically the terminal object but in the case of the category of kk-modules, I would choose :=k\top :=k). Let f:XYf:X \rightarrow Y. We define a fiber object of ff as an object XfX_f together with an epimorphism πf:XXf\pi_f:X \rightarrow X_f (requiring πf\pi_f to be an epimorphism ensures that XfX_f is unique up to isomorphism if it exists) such that the following universal property is satisfied:

For every object ZZ and morphism u:XZu:X \rightarrow Z if for any two morphisms x,y:Xx,y:\top \rightarrow X such that fx=fyf \circ x=f \circ y, we have that ux=uyu \circ x=u \circ y, then there exists a unique morphism u~:XfZ\tilde{u}:X_f \rightarrow Z such that u=u~πfu=\tilde{u} \circ \pi_f.

In most categories of structured sets and homomorphisms, XfX_f should be isomorphic to the image of ff. However, I don't see how the definition of fibre object of a morphism could be equivalent to the definition of image of a morphism in general. I rather expect, but I could be wrong, that only under some hypotheses on C\mathcal{C}, we have can derive a very general first isomorphism theorem which gives that the image of ff is isomorphic to the fibre object XfX_f of ff.

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (Jan 04 2025 at 22:58):

If you allow x,yx,y to range over all generalized elements of XX (which is usually what you'd want to do), then your XfX_f is the coequalizer of the kernel of ff, sometimes called the "regular coimage".

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (Jan 04 2025 at 22:59):

That gives a construction of the usual image (i.e. (regular epi, mono) factorization) in any regular category.

view this post on Zulip Jean-Baptiste Vienney (Jan 04 2025 at 23:00):

Thank you! This is exactly the answer I was looking for.

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (Jan 04 2025 at 23:00):

Where did you get the term "fiber object" for this? It doesn't look like a fiber at all to me.

view this post on Zulip Jean-Baptiste Vienney (Jan 04 2025 at 23:01):

If f:XYf:X \rightarrow Y is a function and xXx \in X, then f1(x)f^{-1}(x) is the fiber of ff at xx and XfX_f is the set of all these fibers. That's why I thought that fiber object is a good name.

view this post on Zulip Jean-Baptiste Vienney (Jan 04 2025 at 23:02):

Maybe it is rather "the object of all fibers".

view this post on Zulip Jean-Baptiste Vienney (Jan 05 2025 at 00:04):

It's weird that every regular category has (regular epi, mono) factorization, but that Top\mathbf{Top} has (regular epi, mono) factorization without being a regular category.

view this post on Zulip Jean-Baptiste Vienney (Jan 05 2025 at 00:12):

(Regular epis are the quotient maps in Top\mathbf{Top}.)

view this post on Zulip Jean-Baptiste Vienney (Jan 05 2025 at 00:21):

Ok, now it feels less weird, seeing that:
Screenshot 2025-01-04 at 7.20.48 PM.png
Regular categories are exactly the categories with (regular epi, mono) factorization + an additional property (which is not satisfied by Top\mathbf{Top}).

view this post on Zulip Mike Shulman (Jan 05 2025 at 17:55):

Normally "fiber object" refers to an analogue of f1(y)f^{-1}(y), namely the pullback of ff along a global element y:1Yy:1\to Y (of the codomain, not the domain).