You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Hello, I have what seems like a beginner's question about adjunctions. Assume we have three adjunctions as shown below:
Assume further that and .
Recall that we have transposition/conjugation operations, i.e. natural bijections
I might be overlooking something but is it automatic that ? If this is not the case, is there a name for this scenario? I've come across this in adjunctions induced by (co)monad morphisms where this is always the case. Maybe it's always true for composition of (co)monadic adjunctions. Any pointers would be appreciated.
The condition that is precisely the condition remaining for the adjunction between and to be the composite of the other two adjunctions. It's not a necessary condition for, given any , we could form a exhibiting by, for instance, composing an automorphism to .
In other words, the condition for an adjunction to be the composite of two others requires this condition, in addition to having the left and right adjoints be composite functors.
I see, thanks.
A followup question: Suppose we have monads and on a category such that has coequalizers of reflexive pairs. Then a monad morphism induces an adjoint pair between the categories of EM algebras (cf. Johnstone 1974):
Is it written up somewhere that this adjoint situation is in fact a composition of two adjunctions (in the same sense as discussed above)?
I don't personally know of a reference, but I also don't see why it should be true: the left adjoint is defined using the reflexive coequalisers in , which are defined only up to isomorphism, so I don't see why the triangle in that diagram involving the left adjoints should commute.
If a diagram of right adjoints commutes, then the corresponding diagram of left adjoints will automatically commute, by uniqueness of adjunctions.
But only up to isomorphism, so that doesn't conflict with what Nathanael said.
I assumed when Tomas said "is" he meant up to isomorphism. Why would you ask for more than that?
Yes, there's some choice involved but as we showed in our technical report the equaliser for free algebras can be given by an explicit formula so that the diagram commutes on the nose.
Separately to that I needed the fact that the composite of the two adjunctions gives the third one so my question is if this fact has been written up somewhere. I was surprised that it is not so trivial and needed the techniques of bimorphisms that we also discuss in the above mentioned technical report.
Mike Shulman said:
I assumed when Tomas said "is" he meant up to isomorphism. Why would you ask for more than that?
If you wanted the assignment from monad morphisms to categories of algebras to be (covariantly) functorial rather than pseudofunctorial, which makes everything simpler. (To be clear, Tomáš asked for composition "in the same sense as discussed above", which involves strict composition of both adjoints.)
Nathanael Arkor said:
If you wanted the assignment from monad morphisms to categories of algebras to be (covariantly) functorial rather than pseudofunctorial, which makes everything simpler.
I'm not considering the category of monad morphisms so I don't understand why this would make any difference :upside_down:.
Either way, I would be glad for any reference, whether that would be in the strict or weak sense. Is there any?
I think I'm slightly confused by what you're asking, which is leading me to not give helpful answers. If you are happy for the adjoints to compose only up to isomorphism, then the additional condition involving the strict equality of the natural isomorphisms defining the adjunctions is unnecessary (because the choices of natural isomorphism are not important if you are reasoning up to isomorphism). As far as I can see, the only reason to require the additional condition is if you want everything to commute strictly. So I expect there is not a reference in the literature, because people are generally happy to reason about adjoints up to isomorphism.
Presumably the condition you are asking for is that the isomorphism is equal to the isomorphism defining the composite adjunction? Is there a reason you want this to hold?
(However, given that you can define in such a way as to make the triangle commute, you should be able to phrase your result as giving a functor from the category of monads whose categories of algebras have reflexive coequalisers, to the coslice category under , which will furthermore form something like a local adjunction with the usual (contravariant) assignment of categories of algebras to monads. This seems like a nice formulation that I have not seen elsewhere.)
Nathanael Arkor said:
Presumably the condition you are asking for is that the isomorphism is equal to the isomorphism defining the composite adjunction? Is there a reason you want this to hold?
Yes, this is precisely all I care about and I don't care all that much about the strictness of the composition (although, as I said, I have it for free). I need this for applications, when proving locality theorems (such as Gaifman locality) in the setting of game comonads. It would be nice if I could just have a reference that proves the above property for monad morphisms (or even better lax monad morphisms/Eilenberg-Moore laws).
(Perhaps someone else can provide a reference, but I expect there is not a reference; in the only contexts I have seen this theorem, the authors are satisfied simply with the existence of the left adjoint.)
Great, thanks a lot!