You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
As stated on nCatLab, the Grothendieck construction (where the codomain is the usual comma category) has a left adjoint which sends a functor . to the functor, which sends an object to the comma category .
We can view the construction of the category of elements as a special type of Grothendieck construction of type . I'm working in a setting where for my example the construction of the category of elements has a left adjoint.
Do you know if this known in larger generality or if there are any other known examples of this?
The inclusion has a left adjoint, so you should be able to get an adjoint for all by applying this pointwise and composing with the first adjunction.
Very nice, thank you! I had no idea about the left adjoint to , thanks!
Mac Lane has said in Sheaves in Geometry and Logic that he was working on the special case of the category of elements before Grothendieck gave that construction. Just a historical note
It turns out that the fact that the discrete Grothendieck construction has a left adjoint was already mentioned in Kelly's Basic concepts of enriched category theory. He even gives an explicit formula in (4.77).
Kelly also mentions that the discrete Grothendieck construction is fully faithful. Do you know if this holds in general, for the (full) Grothendieck construction ?
Also, is there a good reference for the fact that the (discrete) Grothendieck construction is fully faithful? Kelly does not provide any justification. I'm not sure if it was folklore back and if a proof of it appears anywehere in the literature.
The in Kelly is fully faithful because it's the right adjoint of a reflective subcategory, which Kelly mentions just above (4.78).
Yes, I know, he mentions that but he does not give a proof of it (unless I missed something). It is not clear to me from Kelly's writing if this was folklore back then or if he just claimed it and the reader was expected to figure out the details by himself, and now this is attributed to Kelly.
Now when I think about this, the question is basically who proved first that this adjunction restricts to the equivalence with discrete opfibrations...
I don't know the original reference. The fact that discrete opfibrations are a reflective subcategory of is a special case of the [[comprehensive factorization system]].
The general Grothendieck construction is not fully faithful to ; its image is the category of opfibrations and morphisms of opfibrations (preserving opcartesian arrows).
Interesting, thanks!