You're reading the public-facing archive of the Category Theory Zulip server.
To join the server you need an invite. Anybody can get an invite by contacting Matteo Capucci at name dot surname at gmail dot com.
For all things related to this archive refer to the same person.
Mac Lane has a survey of category theory called "Categorical algebra" which is surprisingly broad. In only 60 pages he makes it up to the basic properties of the bar construction and PROP's!
One of the nice results here is the diagonal Yoneda lemma, which I have never heard of before:
Let be a functor. Then
.
How can we interpret this? is the unit object in the monoidal category of profunctors from to itself. So if we regard maps from the unit to as "points" of , then the end of counts its "points."
Nice!
I looked at that survey once, but I should do it again, because I'd understand it better now.
In case people are looking for it:
Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 71 (1965), 40-106, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1090/S0002-9904-1965-11234-4
Patrick Nicodemus said:
Mac Lane has a survey of category theory called "Categorical algebra" which is surprisingly broad. In only 60 pages he makes it up to the basic properties of the bar construction and PROP's!
One of the nice results here is the diagonal Yoneda lemma, which I have never heard of before:
Let be a functor. Then
.How can we interpret this? is the unit object in the monoidal category of profunctors from to itself. So if we regard maps from the unit to as "points" of , then the end of counts its "points."
@Théo and I might want to expand on this :wink: https://arxiv.org/abs/2011.13881
I'm not sure if this is an "interpretation", but another way to say this is that the end of a functor defined on is a weighted limit where the weight is .
I find it curious that Mac Lane wrote that before "category theory", as a name for the field, was established; he never uses the phrase in the review. If you go back and look at the old seminars and proceedings from before the mid 1960s or so, none of them say "category theory". At best, they say "categorical algebra" or "theory of categories".
But by 1971, Mac Lane uses it as the opening words of the preface of Categories for the Working Mathematician. It may have been used informally, but not in print, as far as I can see.
I can find mentions in Math Reviews of the phrase "category theory" from the early 1960s, but not before. And there are relatively few, only 19 mentions before 1966, the year of the La Jolla conference on "Categorical Algebra". In the next two years, mentions more than doubled. In the next four years, mentions had more tripled that. And that brings us to 1971. In the next four years, it had more than doubled, again.
Clearly the field itself was growing rapidly, but it wasn't entirely stagnant in the years 1945–1961. I just think it hadn't been named, yet.
There's a set of typewritten notes from 1965 about a seminar Grothendieck gave on "functorial language" (Introduction au Langage Fonctoriel). When I took a look at it, I found it amusing to see that it's in fact nothing but an introduction to plain category theory! (With some emphasis on abelian categories). I guess "functorial language" may have been another temporary name for the subject at the time, at least in France.
It might be interesting to compare the terms "group theory", "ring theory" and "measure theory", and how they got started. Maybe there needs to be a body of theory, well-organized with certain central definitions and theorems, that someone imagines teaching in a course before a subject of "X theory" gets announced.
Godement also uses this term in Topologie Algebrique et Theorie des Faisceaux.
Damiano Mazza said:
There's a set of typewritten notes from 1965 about a seminar Grothendieck gave on "functorial language" (Introduction au Langage Fonctoriel). When I took a look at it, I found it amusing to see that it's in fact nothing but an introduction to plain category theory! (With some emphasis on abelian categories). I guess "functorial language" may have been another temporary name for the subject at the time, at least in France.
category theory says that we should study mathematical structures in terms of their morphisms, without looking inside the objects. if category theory would practice what it preaches, it would be a theory of functors, without looking inside any categories.
I guess if you take that perspective seriously you end up inventing infinity-categories
Jules Hedges said:
I guess if you take that perspective seriously you end up inventing infinity-categories
but you only study them in terms of the infinity+1 morphisms.
The holistic principle we use to build categories will always force us to go to a higher ordinal..!
I don't think category theory every tells us never to look inside the objects. It just gives us the tools so that we don't have to look inside the objects. For example, we can prove the Snake Lemma in any abelian category without every talking about elements. We can also prove the Snake Lemma in any abelian category by noting that every abelian category is locally isomorphic to R-Mod, and therefore we can use elements. Best of both worlds!
I think this distinction between ‘inside’ and ‘outside’ is somewhat misfounded.
Almost all ‘inside’ descriptions of a thing are really just special kinds of ‘outside’ descriptions (eg how elements of a module are linear maps from the base ring).
Lawvere argues that it's wrong to say that in category theory we don't look inside the objects.
He says we look inside an object using morphisms to it. So the object has elements , but also 'generalized elements' .
And coYoneda says we can completely know an object from what's inside it.
Hmm but there are situations where the category can't see inside things in the sense you're describing, and as a result we can reduce the internal content of the objects to better understand the category. My intended example of this is Galois theory: we have a poset (or category, although one must be careful as I've found out) of field extensions, and that poset isn't rich enough to see all of the structure of the fields; as a result, there's the possibility of finding different objects forming an isomorphic poset, namely subgroups of a group, which makes computation a lot easier.
dusko said:
Damiano Mazza said:
There's a set of typewritten notes from 1965 about a seminar Grothendieck gave on "functorial language" (Introduction au Langage Fonctoriel). When I took a look at it, I found it amusing to see that it's in fact nothing but an introduction to plain category theory! (With some emphasis on abelian categories). I guess "functorial language" may have been another temporary name for the subject at the time, at least in France.
category theory says that we should study mathematical structures in terms of their morphisms, without looking inside the objects. if category theory would practice what it preaches, it would be a theory of functors, without looking inside any categories.
mac laane addresses this here image.png
One I made earlier: Screenshot-2021-11-24-at-18.27.04.png
Nothing like the good old category .
I'm afraid a lot of categories would end up being called ...
Kenji Maillard said:
I'm afraid a lot of categories would end up being called ...
... which would of course be abbreviated to , which is nice because morph is also a verb, so we could write papers in pure syntax, from a one word lexicon, like https://isotropic.org/papers/chicken.pdf